[EM] The path to election reform, was Re:
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
abd at lomaxdesign.com
Mon Dec 8 11:51:35 PST 2008
At 02:13 PM 12/6/2008, Kevin Venzke wrote:
>Hello,
>
>--- En date de : Jeu 4.12.08, Abd ul-Rahman
>Lomax <abd at lomaxdesign.com> a écrit :
> > > Ok, so sincerity doesn't matter. It's a red
> > herring, it's something not
> > > to be dwelled upon.
> >
> > My, my, is this an appeal to the common meaning of
> > "sincerity"? After all we've done to point out
> > the technical meanings and to respond to others who have
> > called these words "terms of art," i.e., not to be
> > taken in their common meanings?
>
>No, it was almost certainly me trying to summarize something you had
>said. I'm pretty sure you have said yourself that sincerity is a red
>herring. Whether you were then using a different meaning of "sincerity,"
>or a different context, is difficult for me to tell.
Sincerity is a red herring when it comes to
expressing preference strength. It's not a red
herring when it comes to preference reversal.
Preference reversal implies a substantial
departure from preference order, which is
explicitly violates. Preference equality (the
extreme) does not violate this, it merely does
not express a preference that the voter indicates
is not significant, for whatever reason. Rather,
it reflects the indeterminacy of rank that
offends so many. Kevin, you are certainly not the first!
> > Voting is a choice, not a sentiment. Consider a voting
> > method as a black box. It has some controls on the outside.
> > You manipulate the controls and you influence the result.
> > How the controls translate to influence is well known, with
> > simple methods, not necessarily with complex ones.
>
>I'm starting to wonder whether this viewpoint is of any use to you.
>It seems to me that perhaps all you can do with it, is argue that the
>placement of the Approval cutoff need not correspond to any absolute,
>abstract preference.
That's correct, but that's not a small thing. As
real human beings, we set the Approval cutoff by
considering the realistic possible outcome set,
which includes a consideration of possibility. We
can imagine some kind of absolute preference,
I've described it in other posts in this series:
it is the zero-knowledge assessment of probable
outcome. This is "strategy" but it isn't
dependent upon the knowledge of how other voters
would vote, and even though it could be
considered theoretically optimal, it's not clear
at all to me that I would vote that way. First of
all, restrict the candidate set to candidates the
*voter* immediately rejects as impossible. No,
Santa Claus is not going to be elected. Probably
all write-in possibilities are excluded except
those the voter thinks might actually get some
other votes. Then, N candidates remain, and the
voter has no assessment of relative probability,
except that they are all, for the voter, nonzero.
Assign a probability of 1/N to each candidate,
and multiple the relative utility estimate by
this. (If assessing the relative utility estimate
is too hard, assume that rank order spreads
relative utility. This turns the vote into a kind
of Borda vote, or based on a Borda vote.) The
expected outcome is the sum of all individual
expected utilities, and the voter would then
approval all candidates with higher expected
utility than that, or possibly equal to that.
Nobody expects anyone to vote that way. However,
note that I've suggested that rating higher than
midrange be considered an acceptance of the
candidate for purposes of determining majority vote. This is equivalent.
Defining midrange as the approval cutoff, then,
with the likelihood that nearly all voters --
except in elections with small N -- will
truncate, not expressing a vote for all
above-midrange candidates, and having a majority
requirement, will encourage but not require "more
sincere" voting, i.e., more expression of all candidates considered acceptable.
But it is much easier to vote by looking only at
candidates with *significant* election
probability, the "math" can usually be done in
one's head, particularly when there are only two
frontrunners. In Approval, those determine the
votes for the rest of the candidates. In Range, they constrain those votes.
> > Certainly a voter may push the buttons
> > "insincerely." But that would mean, to me, that
> > the voter does not seek to maximize the outcome. A vote for
> > a frontrunner in a Plurality election, if the voter would
> > prefer someone else, is that "sincere"?
>
>Either answer is possible.
That's correct. Which means that sincerity in
this meaning is basically meaningless as applied
to votes. Technically, the voter has reversed
preference if the voter does not write in the
name of every candidate the voter prefers to the
election set. However, we normally restrict our
consideration to the set of candidates on the
ballot, and allow that a voter may consider the
election probabilities of all non-ballot
candidates to be zero. Ahem. The voter votes with
consideration of realistic election
probabilities. Thus strategic voting, as it has
been often defined, is inevitable, it's only a
question of what *kind* of strategic voting.
(Disallow write-ins, and then demand that the
voter express all preferences within the set of
candidates on the ballot, you can then return to
some discrimination between strategic and
non-strategic. But that's contrary to higher
democratic norms. Write-ins are, I understand,
generally not allowed outside the U.S. That's one
aspect of democracy that we got right. Other
countries got other aspects. (Note that I don't
consider registration requirements, that all
candidates be *registered*, to be inferior, as
long as registration is simple, can be done up to
the day before the election, and is so low-cost
that the cost is negligible, it would not impeded
any serious candidate -- nor a voter in Asset who
wants to represent himself or herself in
subsequent process. San Francisco has a
"write-in" system like this, in the primaries. It
used to have the same in the runoffs, but, folks,
politics is everywhere. Use it or lose it, defend
it or it *will* be gone. That rule change
excluded a specific candidate, it was challenged,
and the California Supreme Court, a bit to my
surprise, defined a runoff election as being
"part of the same election." That was a possible
conclusion, but a poor one, when we look at
standard deliberative process, which clearly
wants a series of independent elections, and
which allows the electorate, by majority vote, to
postpone the result. The Court clearly followed
the principle that the runoff *must* terminate
with election, no matter what, a principle which
has been raised higher than that of majority
rule. There is a word for this, which I apply
technically: fascist. Mild, to be sure, and
generally moot. It is rare that the write-in
possibility is effectively used in serious contested elections.
> > We can call a vote concealing preference
> > "insincere," but that does, indeed, take the
> > meaning quite away from the common meaning. Note that if the
> > voter bullet votes for the favorite, the voter is similarly
> > concealing other preferences within the rejected category.
> > If equal ranking in the presence of a preference is
> > insincere, then *every Open Voting vote is insincere.*
> > It's *impossible* to vote sincerely, under that view.
> > Which is why the view is actually preposterous.
>
>Well, that's not how I would argue that Approval encourages "insincere"
>voting. But that's a separate issue.
>
>So, one would rather say that every strategic vote is at least at the
>same time sincere.
In Range methods, yes. Not so with ranked
methods, and there's the rub. Yes, if we avoid
calling the choices voters make "preferences" --
which is actually done, that is, on RCV ballots,
for example, they are called "choices" -- then
the concept of sincerity doesn't apply at all,
except that we can still assume that the voter is
"sincerely" attempting to influence the result in
some way, even if it is just to show contempt or
silliness. Yes, I deliberately voted for Mickey
Mouse. That shows what I think of the choices presented to me on the ballot.
But this isn't useful. What is useful is to
consider preference reversal "insincere," and to
allow that there are many different sincere votes otherwise.
These sincere votes may be chosen according to
improvement of expectation strategy, but this is
different from strategy that reverses
preferences; in particular, this strategy, either
partial or fully optimized, averages over many
voters to approach what would be the average
fully sincere vote (positive expectation
Approval, or accurate relative utility Range.)
Preference reversal has weird effects that I won't go into.
"Strategic voting" in Range corresponds to
ordinary real-life decision-making process,
where, faced with multiple choices, we assess
which ones are reasonably possibilities and
assign our assets to those, considering relative
probabilities, to one degree or other. It's not
some strange new thing that voters have to learn
in order to be able to vote intelligently.
>One could say that this is a bit of a trick. We can say that Approval
>doesn't have "insincere strategic" votes, due to the way the method works.
>But clearly it can only work this way by lacking a great degree of
>expressiveness.
Of course. But pure ranked methods also lack
expressiveness, sometimes as much as Approval.
You want full expressiveness, you want high-resolution Range.
Note that Relative Utilitarianism -- a method of
preference amalgamation, strictly, not a voting
method in itself -- uses von Neumann-Morganstern
utilities, which preserve preference order unless
there is zero probability for an outcome, in
which case the preference strength involving that
outcome goes to zero. Preference is never
reversed even with a zero probability. Turned
into a voting system, RU implies Range, and the
authors, Dhillon and Mertens, specifically
suggest Approval as a practical appplication
where the voter decides between 0 and 1 for each
candidate, maximizing expected outcome.
The decision of where to set the approval cutoff
is specifically left to the voter, and likewise
how to weight the votes in higher resolution
expression. Given sufficient resolution, I would
preserve any discernable preference, Range 100 is
more than enough unless there were a ton of
candidates. (And with a ton of candidates, it's
highly unlikely that I could knowledgeably rank that many.)
This constrains the Range votes and, with broadly
distributed candidates, makes them *relatively* deterministic.
> > The question before us is really this: is it better that
> > voters vote "strategy free," which is equivalent
> > to voting "zero knowledge," or is it better that
> > they adjust their votes according to their understanding of
> > the context, i.e., what other voters think.
>
>First of all I don't know what you mean when you say that voting
>"strategy free" is the same as voting "zero knowledge."
This was developed through this discussion. Zero
knowledge means that the voter cannot use an
expectation as to how others will vote, because
the voter does not know. It's a standard concept,
and a definition of strategic voting using it is
reasonable, if perhaps misleading, improperly applied.
Pure ranked methods, particularly if equal
ranking is allowed, allows easy zero knowledge
voting. Order the candidates in sequence by
preference of election. (Strictly speaking, it is
the election that is preferred, not the
candidates, and the difference affects where I
rank unknown candidates.) If there is no
discernable preference, equal rank. Note that
forced ranking, equal ranking not allowed, does
not allow sincere voting, because it forces the
expression of a preference where not exists. If
we want sincere voting to be possible, we *must*
allow equal ranking. And that makes the method
into a form of Approval! -- because it can be
voted that way. (Though other aspects may make this undesirable to the voter.)
(In general, I prefer allowing the voter to
choose the "voting system," to a degree. I.e.,
equal ranking should be allowed. A voter should
be allowed to cast a Later No Harm compliant
vote, in substance if not in full effect. For
example, any method which requires a runoff with
majority failure is not LNH compatible, strictly.
But in substance, it can be. Terrill Bouricius'
bill in the Vermont legislature explicity
claimed, in the ballot instructions, LNH
compliance, though it wasn't strictly true,
because a majority was required or the top three
went to the legislature for resolution by secret ballot vote.)
Range with approval cutoff and sufficient
resolution can be voted as ranked, including
using a Borda-type distribution of ratings,
Approval, or even Plurality. The ballot is the
most expressive of any that I've seen proposed.
That freedom of expression, of course, means that
we cannot derive the voter's vote simply by
knowing the voter's preferences and preference
strengths. The voting is a possibly complex
decision, unpredictable. But very usable!
>My answer to this question is that I'm not sure; I think it depends; I
>also think it's probably a moot point.
It's not moot when words like "sincerity" and
"strategic voting" are bandied about as if they
had fixed moral implications! That's what I keep hammering down....
> > Any method which satisfies Later No Harm must not provide
> > this information, or, at least, must not use it. This is why
> > Later No Harm is actually, itself a poor election criterion.
>
>I think that is premature. Of course this makes sense if we're only
>discussing FPP and IRV, and there aren't many other choices. But the
>methods MMPO and Woodall's DSC method satisfy LNHarm, and it wouldn't
>be true to say that they don't use the lower preferences. They just
>are careful to not use those preferences against the voter.
Later No Harm can, in some conditions, remove one
cause of bullet voting, causing votes to become
more expressive. I'm not saying that it is
valueless. But election criteria, in general, are
analyzed as absolutes, and any voting system
which contains what I consider essential for true
result optimization must violate LNH. It's the
rigid requirement that is a problem. Those
methods, if they satisfy LNH, must sometimes make
seriously poor decisions, because the information
they need to optimize results is missing, and
*they do not allow it to be expressed.*
Using lower preferences of a voter is not
"against the voter," and that's part of the LNH
myth. It is "for the voter." Just not exclusively
for the voter's first preference. If you would
not be pleased by an election result, don't vote
for it! Demand, instead, that the voting system
require a majority vote to complete. You are then
essentially consenting to the inconvenience of a
real runoff by truncating and not expressing
lower preferences. It's your choice.... Depriving
the voter of reasonable options, and, in
particular, depriving the majority of the ability
to cause election failure, is a serious violation
of democratic principles, we have too long and
too often tolerated in the name of efficiency, a false dichotomy.
> > Voters may desire to vote Later No Harm, but this is the
> > kind of concealment of preference that reduces election
> > efficiency. It is a concealment of true preference
> > strengths, so, again, any method which follows Later No Harm
> > has *required* the concealment of preferences. We avoid some
> > level of strategic voting by *requiring* all voters to vote
> > that way.
>
>Ok. That is an interesting argument. It seems to work in favor of Approval
>against both IRV and Range.
This would be Saari's argument for Borda as well.
Note that this isn't *my* argument, I consider it
specious and anti-democratic. In order to avoid
the harm of strategic voting, we require all
voters to vote strategically, thus
institionalizing that inaccuracy. It's not
terribly harmful, though, because Approval votes
do average out, normally, to results approximating Range results.
> > But if some voters conceal preference, and others do not,
> > with a good method, the results are better than if *all*
> > voters conceal preference. Further, a good method allows the
> > expression of all significant preferences without harm to
> > the voter. "Harm" must mean, not that the voter
> > fails to get their first preference, but that the preference
> > strength between that candidate and the winner is not
> > minimized. Since IRV is not monotonic, as an example, it can
> > seriously harm the voter's interest if that is expressed
> > sincerely. The only reasonable defense against this
> > criticism of IRV is that this is rare.
>
>That's not very generous. I can think of a couple of defenses. One would
>be to point out that it is necessitated by the other criteria that IRV
>satisfies. All things being equal, I consider LNHarm more desirable than
>monotonicity, for instance.
I, and certainly some experts, consider LNH to
cause serious harm. Absolutely, it's undesirable
in deliberative process, someone who insists on
not disclosing lower preferences until their
first preference has become impossible would be
considered a fanatic or selfish. That's a trait
I'd like to allow, but not encourage!
I'm not *specifically* offended by monotonicity
failure, in the same way, but it would depend on
the social utility damage caused by the failure.
Monotonicity is an Arrovian axiom, and for good
reason. It's a sign of something seriously wrong with the method.
Here we see an example of the criterion-based
judgment of voting systems. It's a fundamentally
flawed and subjective approach, devoid of and not
susceptible to measurement (except as to
frequency assessment, given enough ballot and
poll data, or simulations). That is, we might be
able to objectively predict how often IRV would
violate monotonicity, but that gives us no
objective way to assess the *seriousness* of the failure itself.
But there is a way, which is Bayesian regret,
which is itself founded on the old utilitarian
concept, the greatest good for the greatest
number, converted to a sum of utilities approach.
Contrary to so many shallow claims, it is
possible to define interpersonally compatible
utilities of a kind useful in social choice, and
that's what Dhillon and Mertens show, and further
that these utilities can be used in the only
Social Welfare Function that is compatible with
the Arrovian set (excepting only that IIA is
redefined in a reasonable way to apply it to a sum of ratings method).
Allowing voters discretion to vote these
utilities, then, allows them to approach, through
their free choices, an ideal voting system. The
system simply takes their votes *as if they were
sincere*, and optimizes the results. "Insincere
voting" in this system simply means not troubling
to -- or deliberately concealing -- express fine
preferences. It's foolish to conceal a major
preference in such a system, unless it is a moot one.
> > Yet that this does harm can only even be perceived if we
> > have sincere Range votes, for all voters, to compare the
> > results with. Range strategic voting does not harm results
> > to the point where they become as inefficient as those of
> > less accurate methods.
>
>If you're talking about simulations now, this doesn't seem to be true.
>"Strategic" Approval (however that was defined) was worse than the
>sincere Condorcet method. You can say that it isn't fair to compare
>strategic Approval to sincere Condorcet, but there aren't any serious
>alternatives for comparison. It's an "unknown" at best for Approval.
First of all, normally the Condorcet Criterion
works. That's one reason why it has such appeal.
The simulations show average results. No, it's
not "unknown," the simulations show comparisons.
It's true that it is possible that some kinds of
optimized Approval, possibly those used in the
simulations -- it's totally unclear to me what
"strategic Approval," but presumably this means
applying certain fixed strategies, may
underperform, on average, sincere Condorcet, but
I'd want to look at the nature of the failures.
I'd be surprised if the differences were large. I
should look at the simulation results again. Note
that I was describing Range Voting, not Approval,
but Range with full strategic voting fades into
Approval, so, sure, a totally unrealistic extreme
of Range could possibly underperform a Condorcet
method. But that's not in the simulations, and
while Approval is a Range method, it's the
absolute extreme in the unexpressive end.
>I'm not sure we really need simulations for this. I try to imagine how
>insincere Condorcet voters would have to be, to reduce the quality of
>the method to the equivalent of only having two rank levels.
You want lots of rank levels, you want Range or
Borda (almost equivalent, but Range fixes some
Borda problems.) Approval works better than you
might expect because those rank levels are chosen
by many voters and average out to show much more
information about the voter set than individual voters can express.
(How insincere? Preference reversal is black and
white, it happens or it doesn't. The difficult
with Condorcet isn't that, it is that trivial
preferences are necessarily equated with large
ones. Now, if the Condorcet method allows equal
ranking, it is really a more sophisticated form
of Approval, or perhaps you'd prefer to say Range, just as Bucklin is.
>What I am unable to get past, is that there is no theoretical reason
>for Range voters to vote "accurately" other than that we can agree that
>we would like them to. So the accurate, non-strategic Range voters are
>either voting in error, or they are choosing to play nice.
Choosing to play nice is a strategic vote that
one accomplishes, in Range, by voting, as closely
as possible, a measure of one's satisfaction with
each candidate. The theoretical reason for voters
to do this? That it works, that many or even most
people will do it, quite likely, that it's easier
than deciding pure rank, what else do you need.
Absolutely, voters will deviate from the
"accurate" vote, with or without intention. They
will approximate. They will bullet vote. They
will spread. They will do it all. And all of it,
together, is more expressive of the true position
of the electorate than is possible with a pure
ranked method. Take Borda, allow equal ranking,
it's the same. Range defaults, with full-on,
high-knowledge strategic voting, to Approval.
(The voter will vote for the candidate where it
is possible for the voter to improve the outcome,
which, the voter will know with high precision,
even certainty. (total:knowledge: it's a tie
without the vote or the vote will create a tie).
Why call this Approval and not FPTP? Because that
voter can still vote, in addition, for any
candidate preferred to the effective maximizer,
and I think almost all such voters would.
Otherwise their vote is not sincere, it would
reverse preference but since it is harmless to
express that preference, and is, in addition,
insurance against being wrong about the true
frontrunner(s), voters will do it. Why not be more sincere if it is harmless?
Strategic voting in Approval is actually easier
to predict than so-called sincere voting. For the
majority of voters in real election situations,
most will know who the frontrunners are.
>I think it would be reckless to just assume we would get this, so I
>cautiously view Range as exactly the same as Approval. Approval is in
>my top 5 list, if I were able to propose something. But I have
>reservations about it, and think we can probably do better without losing
>anything.
But that's actually silly, Kevin. Every
indication we have is that some fraction of
voters will vote intermediate ratings; for many
of them, it is strategically harmless or even
advantageous (as "insurance.") Further, the
existence of unpredictable numbers of fractional
votes dithers the result, making ties much less
possible, and we can assume that intermediate
votes are *relatively* sincere. To consider
higher resolution range as "exactly the same" as Approval is preposterous.
Now, Approval is in your "top five" list. Various
methods have various social and political costs
to implementation. Which one is more accessible?
Which one costs practically nothing and,
remember, for a very low-cost reform, the issue
is whether or not it could cause serious damage.
Approval's alleged "failures" are that (1) it can
reduce to Plurality, allegedly. Except that this
isn't the case when there is a spoiler candidate,
we will almost certainly substantial numbers of
additional votes from supporters of the spoiler.
And, compared to Plurality, this result is
clearly harmless, it hasn't made the situation
worse. SU estimates show very substantial
improvements, comparable to much more expensive
methods. It's probably the
biggest-bang-for-the-buck method. Comparing
Approval to Condorcet is the wrong comparison
and, in fact, there is no real conflict.
Start with Approval, you'd go to
equal-ranking-allowed Condorcet, which is more
accurate than pure ranked Condorcet. I'd be
astonished if it were not higher SU than pure ranked Condorcet.
Further, allowing equal ranking will certainly
reduce the number of spoiled ballots. While some
of that information is bogus, on average counting
it reflects voter intention better than
discarding it. (Consider Florida 2000; if the
votes which had overvoted Gore and Buchanan -- as
a rather obvious result of bad ballot design --
had been counted, Buchanan would have gotten some
extra votes, which would have been totally
harmless. Gore would have gotten the same number
of additional votes, *most of which were
doubtless the intended vote.* It's a bit of a
shame that the U.S. courts don't allow the use of
statistical methods to recover intended votes,
but rather insist on the pure examination of each
vote individually. If there is a hanging chad on
some other punch than Gore, for example, and Gore
is clearly punched, or even equally badly
punched, there is a certain probability that the
vote was intended for Gore. It *wasn't* intended
for Bush, unless Bush had the hanging chad. If
so, the voter was abstaining, if the vote was
intentional, from the real election, and it's
moot. You could count both, as I would do. It
could be argued that such votes should be counted
fractionally, but some counting is better than
none! Politics, unfortunately, affects all of
this, so that the issue doesn't become what best
discerns the intention of the electorate, as
expressed by the votes and the method, but who
wins. Anyone here who thinks that the U.S.
Supreme Court in late 2000 made its decision
purely on the basis of legal principles, please
raise your hand! (Some who supported the decision
have even written, you are surprised that the Court is political? Get over it!)
> > In an election like this, I'd always have a runoff.
>
>If you simply have a runoff, what's to stop clever candidates from running
>with a clone? Do you think these candidates' supporters would become
>offended by this behavior?
Hello? A clone would not affect the Range winner,
essentially. Range satisfies clone independence,
under reasonable assumptions. Remember, clones
impact campaign costs, very much of successful
campaigning is as simple as gaining positive name
recognition. Divide that among two candidates?
Bad idea, quite likely to cause a loss. In any
case, cloning would not affect whether or not the
clone or cloned candidate would beat the Range
winner pairwise. I have *not* proposed top-two
Range. What I've proposed is a method where
majority failure, i.e., the failure of a majority
to approve of a winner (which could be defined as
voting above a set "approval cutoff," and the
voters know that. For example, in Range 3, with
votes of -1, -1/3, +2/3, 1, it could be defined
that any positive vote was approval. (which with
standard approval strategy makes perfect sense).
If a runoff is forced, it would not be among the
top two Range winners. That would be vulnerable
to cloning, though only in a very narrow sense.
(It could be argued that in this case, either of
these candidates is the best winner, this is pure
Range, so cloning is really moot. If you can get
there, you don't need cloning, and you just made
the campaigning harder.) No, it would be between
a Range winner and any candidate who beats the
Range winner pairwise, who, with fixed
preferences assumed and the same voters, would
win a runoff. If there are two of these, ideally
they would all be in the runoff, but I'd pick the
Condorcet winner among them, and if they were
members of a cycle, I'd pick the one with the highest Range rating.
Pretty difficult to game this system in a truly
negative way. It encourages voters to express all
sincere preferences except possibly the truly
moot, provided that the Range method has
sufficient resolution. Low-res range would have a
preference marker. I called Approval with
preferred marker A+, and if this was used in
determining the winner, I called it A+/PW, PW for
pairwise. But there is no advantage to this, that I can see, over ER-Bucklin.
The immediate election reforms I recommend are
(1) top two runoff, or specifically keeping
runoffs where they exist. (2) Approval or
Bucklin, and particularly one of these as the
primary in TTR, and possibly the secondary, where
they might be plurality methods, which I still
don't like, personally. I'd use Asset to resolve
a continued problem. Far more efficient, and fully democratic.
In any case, allowing equal ranking is essential
to allowing a fully expressive vote. Range
without that is simply Borda count, a good method
on its own. We really wonder why Saari seems to
have not realized that Range is just Borda with
some tweaks allowing fuller expression. I never
cease to be amazed by election reformers who
think they know better than the voters how voters
*should* vote. They do *not* trust democracy.
> > The point is that, yes, if the isolated voters are
> > exaggerating their expressed preference, the overall result
> > has not been optimized. But by how much did it fall short?
> > Very, very little. In the Range 100 example, overall
> > satisfaction, assuming that the isolated voter really had
> > the same preferences as the others, only reversed, has been
> > damaged by 9999 minus 9801 = 198, which is 2.0%.
>
>I'm not sure how you can tell whether this is big or small. Typically
>one's vote makes no difference at all.
It is a ritual. We are talking possible results.
After all, Keven, you are concerned about Later
No Harm. How much of a consideration is that? How
likely is it that the voters' additional vote --
which must be taken as a kind of approval unless
you force full ranking -- will harm the voter?
The most it will do is produce less benefit! The
whole concept is confused, in fact.
> > Indeed. What I've been pushing for is precision in the
> > definition, not just the sloppy use of a very hot-button
> > word without careful definition and application. Many
> > writers, early on, noted that "sincere vote" with
> > Approval did not have a clear meaning, that there wasn't
> > just one "sincere vote," there were many.
>
>By "writers" are you talking about published articles, or EM participants?
Here, published articles.
> > Within
> > that many, though, most didn't define some as
> > "sincere" and others not. That came, I think,
> > later, where writers started to assume that the voter had
> > some absolute approval cutoff, and was concealing that by
> > voting differently. This is underneath most of what I've
> > seen as criticism of Approval on the basis of
> > "vulnerability to strategy."
>
>The criticism could rather be that Approval *requires* strategy, which
>means it isn't clear how to translate sincere preferences into an
>Approval vote, which means that, once you have identified the Approval
>winner, it is extremely difficult to explain why that is a good winner,
>in terms that relate back to the original sincere preferences/utilities.
Not difficult at all, actually. *If a majority
was found.* This is why if I have my choice
between TTR and Approval, in spite of the
theoretical advantages of Approval, I'd go for
TTR, it is closer to an even more intelligent
method of aggregating preferences. Of course, TTR
gets even better with an Approval primary, and
probably even better with a Bucklin one. It even
gets better with a 2-winner STV primary, with a
single winner determined if that candidate gains
a majority. But Bucklin is much easier to count,
and the practical difference, in terms of outcome
quality, might hinge on how often LNH influences
Bucklin voters to avoid adding second or lower
preferences. I think it would, in fact, have little harmful effect.
We had, in the U.S., and still have, in some
places, a method which is Condorcet compliant and
which is almost exactly what Robert's Rules of
Order actually recommends, instead of the IRV
that FairVote asserts. It's top-two runoff with
write-in votes allowed in the runoff. The primary
is a convenient and *non-binding* way of
determining ballot position, when needed. There
are two elections (not one as the California
Supreme Court asserted in ruling on the San
Francisco exclusion of runoffs -- which only
affected, I think, one election.) The winner must
gain a majority in the first election or a
plurality in the second, and almost always that
is a majority, not a mere plurality, which is why
I call it close to the RRO recommendation. They
recommend repeating the election, which might
mean new nominations, withdrawals, compromises.
No eliminations. If write-ins are allowed, there
are no eliminations, actually; if there was a
Condorcet winner in the primary, by significant
preference strength, a write-in campaign is set up to be successful.
But we can clearly do even better. For now,
though, we should keep the best system we have in
the U.S., TTR, (setting aside STV in Cambridge),
and work on making it better. Just allowing Open
Voting would make it a lot better, using Bucklin,
with it's noble history, even better.
> > We need to define "sincere vote," as it applies
> > to voting systems, using a uniform definition that applies
> > to all methods, or we cannot determine whether a method
> > encourages "sincerity," or treats sincere votes
> > properly. What are sincere votes?
>
>I don't think we will be able to define it. I don't think we need to,
>on this list. We can define what we mean when we make the claim.
Sure. My goal here is to point out that it is
often used without that precision, and then knee-jerk conclusions are derived.
>If we could agree on what "sincere vote" means, then yes, we could go
>around advertising our methods as certified as Strategy-Free. And this
>would help us gain followers.
Approval was called that, in peer-reviewed
publications. So ... they changed the meaning of
"strategic voting." Clever, don't you think?
> > What we need to do is look at how systems treat (1)
> > preference reversal, i.e., clear insincerity, (2)
> > concealment of preference, and (3) fully sincere votes.
>
>I think you are breaking this down more than is desirable. I'm not sure
>these categories are useful. #3 is probably meaningless under Approval,
>so that gets us nowhere. Regarding #2: Isn't there (or couldn't there
>be) a qualitative difference between IRV's treatment of lower preferences,
>forced compression under Approval, and, say, truncation?
It can be given a meaning. There is a way of
defining a "sincere approval cutoff," as positive
election expectation. But it's not necessarily
the best actual voting pattern, if the voter has
zero knowledge, even though it is an optimal
strategy. Rather zero-knowledge situations, where
the initial poll is all that voters have, and
where further process will follow if there is
majority failure, encourage tighter approval,
even bullet voting. Approval theorists worked
this out long ago, actually, particularly on this
list, conceiving of Approval as a series of polls culminating in an election.
I defined a Range method where approvals cascade
down the ratings, starting with the highest,
shifting an approval cutoff down one step at a
time until a majority is found. Is there a name
for that? Seems someone else may have proposed
that. If the voter specifies it, substantial LNH compliance can be gained.
>Though, when you aren't aware of the assumption that voters may play
>nice under Range, saying that "strategic voting can harm results"
>is happily not very meaningful.
It's been precisely defined. If you define the
ideal result as the absolute SU maximizer, or,
alternatively, as the normalized SU maximizer,
then concealing the preferences on which this is
based necessarily makes it possible to miss that
winner. Thus Range doesn't have zero Bayesian
regret. If we use absolute utilities (which may
be the soundest approach, perhaps defined on the
"universal candidate set" that Dhillon and
Mertens talk about), normalized, we can get a
true optimization. Voters may optimize their
personal expectation above that vote, though, as
D/M note, they even suggest it and name it: Approval voting.
So, it's reasonable, in fact, to say that
Approval voting "requires" a kind of strategy. In
fact, though, it only requires that to maximize
personal impact on the real election. Voters can
provide useful information short of that, and, as
all the information provided is sincere, it
helps. It simply doesn't help all the way.
>What you're talking about here isn't even "playing nice," it's more
>like using lower ratings as loose change to toss into an (inadequate)
>street musician's hat. I'm not clear on what motivates that either.
>I don't think I've ever wanted to communicate to a candidate that they
>aren't acceptable (i.e. worse than what I expect out of the election
>after considering both frontrunners' odds), but should keep trying.
Why did voters vote for Nader in 2000? Were they
purely stupid? You may never have voted this way,
but other real people do. Why do voters bother to
vote for minor parties, ever? Do you think that
most of them imagine that candidate could win?
You are right. Existing methods don't allow that
kind of communication, so, of course, you've not
even though about the possible value. I may think
a candidate not ready for prime time, but up and
coming. If the candidate is moot, though, I might
rate the candidate higher than otherwise, and
there are lots of possible reasons for doing
this. That I prefer one candidate and would not
like to see my vote for another reduce the
election chances of that candidate, hence I don't
"approve" of the second candidate, surely you
understand this. That's the legitimate thinking behind LNH.
> > If we want optimal results, we need to find ways to
> > encourage sincere voting, that's true. But we need that
> > preference strength information to optimize results.
>
>What if you can't get it? I think you can only get it indirectly, by
>forcing voters to make strategic decisions.
Perhaps. However, we get *some* of it from
looking at the Range vote patterns, and simple
summation does a pretty good job of it.
Preference analysis extracts an additional
increment, and a runoff actually tests sincere
preference strength. This keeps being overlooked,
maybe I need to mention it more!
> > Only with Range, though, does it even become possible to
> > exaggerate preferences. And the meaning of
> > "exaggeration" is unclear, we have to define what
> > a "fully sincere" range vote is, and that is not
> > particularly easy.
>
>Well, I think it's fairly easy. Especially since you are totally free,
>as far as I can see, to declare that normalized ratings are sincere.
Yes. Usually that's allowed, though these ratings
are not "fully accurate." Absolute utilities
would be fully accurate, but could not be used
unless we have an auction system or similar.
Politically, as Dhillon and Mertens note,
one-person, one-vote is a necessity. Hence
normalized utilities are as close as we can get.
In simulations, we can still study using
non-normalized utilities (they must still be
normalized in some sense, but only with a
universal candidate set, that is the Dhillon-Mertens approach.)
> > But we can say, as with Approval, that
> > any vote that does not reverse preference is not insincere.
> > And then we say that "fully sincere" means that
> > preference strength is expressed with reasonable accuracy,
> > fidelity to true underlying utilities, and thus useful for
> > finding compromises assuming that further information cannot
> > be obtained (as with a runoff).
>
>You can do this, but as soon as critics realize that in order to speak
>your language they need to use the concept of "fully sincere," you'll
>find you haven't gotten very far from them.
I didn't invent that language, Smith uses it. It
means with accurate disclosure of preference
strengths, which, of course, must be defined, and
it is generally defined to be zero-knowledge.
It's not modified by probabilities. It is the raw
data on which VNM utilities are determined by application of probabilities.
(Dhillon and Mertens use a lottery approach,
voters are voting on lotteries, which is sound. A
vote has a certain probability of affecting a
result, one "invests" one's vote in that probability and utility combination.)
> > Range makes it *possible* to move beyond the assumption of
> > fixed preferences.
>
>Well, the Range *ballot* does.
Yup. That's what I mean.
> > It does not guarantee that we will, but I
> > don't see that, when it does not, it has therefore been
> > a net harm over fixed preference systems.
>
>Certainly difficult to say for sure.
I've never seen an actual assertion. FairVote
gives an example where Range works just fine, and
simply assumes that it is a preposterously bad
outcome because Plurality with sincere voting,
zero knowledge, would result in 99:1 for one
result; but Range gives the other result.
However, real deliberative process, with the
stated utilities, would be quite likely to come
up with the second result as well, hence my
thinking that it is very important to remember
that we only tolerate advanced election methods
because we think we need to make a decision in
one ballot, which is a *severe* constraint;
fortunately for us, perhaps, Plurality usually
gets the right one! -- because of pre-election
process. Have a truly open election like
California's election of the Terminator, it's a
mess. But he might have won with IRV, for
example. The Plurality leader usually does. (And
he might have won with any non-majority required
method that is on the table. He was very popular,
really. I even like him, he's not so predictable by knowing he's a Republican.)
> > Plurality is generally considered to satisfy the Majority
> > Criterion. (Actually, I think Woodall may have concluded
> > differently, but I don't have the reference handy.)
>
>Well, I have told you at least twice that the reason Woodall says
>Plurality fails Majority is because his "Majority" criterion is not
>the same.
I knew that. I wasn't repeating it for your
benefit, but for the general readership. In this
case, I didn't want to repeat what I knew,
because I was not certain of the details.
>Here is an example.
>
>7 A
>6 B>C
>5 C>B
>
>According to Woodall's Majority criterion, the winner must be B or C,
>because more than half of the voters are solidly committed to the set
>of candidates {B,C}. Plurality elects A and thus fails the criterion.
>
>It would be misleading to say that Woodall says that Plurality fails
>the Majority criterion without clarifying that he doesn't use the same
>definition of the criterion.
That's right. I certainly didn't say the opposite! I said "may."
> > So why is Approval considered to fail the M.C.? Believe me,
> > I've been around and around this in other discussion.
> > It's because multiple approvals are considered sincere
> > votes, so the voter has voted sincerely. And voting
> > sincerely has been considered the necessity in deciding MC
> > compliance. Why was that the definition?
>
>Actually most of us define criteria to avoid referring to sincerity at
>all. The real question is how to interpret the approval ballot as a
>rank ballot.
Which, of course, can only be done in an
extremely limited way. It is a rank ballot, with
two ranks, equal ranking allowed. (Plurality is
the same, but with the top rank being exclusive,
hang the preference strength, and the bottom rank requiring equal ranking.)
>It is certainly possible to say that Approval satisfies Majority, but
>it is at least as possible to say that it doesn't. It you interpret
>the approval cutoff as something external to the underlying rank ballot,
>then it surely doesn't.
That's right. Except that then you are stuck with "sincerely."
The voter expresses rank. The wording of the MC
was "If a majority of voters rank A above all other candidates, A must win."
Then we have the unstated assumption: the voters
vote this rank "sincerely." They do not conceal it or reverse it.
If a method allows them to express it -- both
Plurality and Approval allow the same expression
of it -- then it would seem that we'd consider
Approval to satisfy the criterion.
As I've said, we've gone around and around on
this. This is why we need to examine sincerity.
In order to consider whether or not a method
satisfies a criterion that depends on something
other than the votes, we need to specify how the
other thing is translated to votes.
If we claim that the voter may have a preference,
conceal it in Approval, and therefore the
preference does not prevail, and the method
fails, we then have a problem: No method can
guarantee that the voter expresses a necessary
preference. So every method would fail.
Definitely, the problem can be solved, one can
make up a definition of the criterion such that
Approval fails. But wait a minute? Weren't voting
systems criteria supposed to be objective methods
for comparing voting systems. If we can flip
compliance by manipulating the definitions, we've
lost the objectivity. And that, in fact,
happened. And the whole voting system criterion
approach to comparing voting systems, while
useful in some ways, is thoroughly defective in
terms of practical assessment of systems.
Criteria are absolutes, they are pass/fail. A
method may fail a criterion, but it is moot if
this is effectively impossible in real elections.
So criterion failure is no proof of method
unsuitability, and it becomes your important
criteria vs my important criteria, and there is
no resolution. And with ranked methods, of
course, we run headlong into Arrow's theorem.
But with sum of ratings systems we can move beyond that.
I'm saying that we should, in fact, agree that
there has been only one method (or family of
methods, more accurately) proposed for assessing
voting system quality, and that is the sum of
voter utilities approach of Smith et al. This
approach can produce *measures* of voting system
quality. While it could theoretically be done
with real elections, practical limitations leave
us with simulations; simulations are far more
powerful than constructed scenarios to show
system failures, because the constructed
scenarios do not address frequency, simulations
do. Sure, the models used in simulations should
be examined for reasonable correspondence to real voter behavior.
But it's all we have.
This approach, however, gives a natural edge to
Range Voting, because the method is, itself, a
means of estimating the social utilities, and
thus it is pratically by definition, more likely
to be optimal. That is, of course, not the end of
the question, and my own work has led me to the
conclusion that hybrid methods can improve on
pure Range by encouraging more accurate
expression of relative utilities, and testing the
preferences when there is a clue that they
haven't been sufficiently expressed. Condorcet
failure is such a clue. We cannot distinguish,
without a runoff, unless we find a different and
better way of encouraging accurate utilities,
between a true Condorcet result with significant
preference strength, and one based on small
preferences and hence safely disregarded in
choosing the Range winner. A runoff tests that.
I've claimed -- and this is, I think, original
with me, that a genuine Range winner, the
absolute utility maximizer, has an edge in any
runoff. To my knowledge, no one else has
confirmed this as a reasonable hypothesis, but
the theory indicates it pretty clearly.
Weak preference strength equals less motivation
to turn out, and higher possibility of voter
change of mind. Both of these effects favor a
genuine Range winner over the Condorcet winner.
What we want to discover is the situation,
relatively rare, where preferences come up with a
clearly poor result, a Condorcet winner, perhaps,
but by weak preference strength, such that the
net "happiness" of the society is significantly
better with another winner; I've used the Pizza
election to show this. Quite simply, healthy
societies do not operate by pure majority or
plurality preference, they take preference
strength into account, they must. Hence the
Condorcet and Majority criteria, taking without
reference to preference strength, must fail in
any method which optimizes results accurately.
(Examples have been adduced which show this, with
situations where nearly everyone would agree that
the majority preference is far short of being the optimal winner.)
> > It wasn't mentioned in the early definitions. In fact,
> > those definitions did not even mention the possible gap
> > between voter preferences and voter votes.
>
>They should not mention them, in my opinion.
So do you define the criterion purely on the
votes? You are aware, of course, that this would
imply that Approval satisfies the Majority Criterion?
Without some specified method of converting voter
preferences (i.e., mental states or underlying
utility converted to ranks) and actual votes
based on them, we cannot assess method compliance.
> > Why is all this important? Because these terms are bandied
> > about as if they condemn a method. "Rewards insincere
> > voting!" "Fails the Majority Criterion!"
> > "Vulnerable to strategic voting." I just saw
> > someone write that, sure, with "sincere votes,"
> > range is an ideal method, but "because it is vulnerable
> > to strategic voting, I cannot support it for public
> > elections."
>
>I don't really see what the big problem is. Even if you don't like the
>terms being "bandied about" you can at least understand the criticism
>being made.
Sure. And I can criticize it as unfounded, based
purely on a knee-jerk response to a behavior
*assumed* to be bad. It's not a matter of not
liking people's writing or speech. It's a matter
of the harm it can do. People are influenced by
this language, they make decisions based on it.
Majority Criterion failure, for example, with
Approval, is a common reason for rejection. Yet
Approval doesn't fail the MC in real-world
political election scenarios unless we are
extraordinarily lucky. In Florida 2000, for
example, it would take a significant number of
voters, more than those who vote for neither Bush
nor Gore, to approve both of them. I'd say that
would be just about impossible. It's an example
of how strict criterion compliance can be very
misleading. Multiple majorities is not a major
problem with approval; but if we think it is,
it's easy to fix. Hold a runoff, just as with
majority failure. But we already have Approval
voting in limited circumstances in the U.S., and
the precedent is that when there are multiple
majorities, the one with the most votes wins.
That's law in at least a few states.
>You don't need the term "Majority Criterion" to understand the criticism
>that Approval can fail to elect the favorite candidate of a majority
>even when the voters are not being fools. Won't happen often? Doesn't
>matter. That's how criteria work, as you know. It's not a wording problem.
The question is the damage done when it happens.
The "damage" is that a candidate is elected who
was, in spite of not being preferred by a
majority, was "accepted" by a larger majority.
That is quite arguably a better result. The
assumption is that MC failure is a bad result,
the criterion wasn't really designed to deal with multiple majorities.
And you are correct. How often it happens is
irrelevant to voting systems criteria. My point.
Could be one election out of a billion, no
matter. It fails because we can construct a
totally ridiculous scenario that it fails in.
And, now, in a real, and actually practical
Social Welfare Function, such an outcome is
actually irrelevant. It would not affect the
real-world value of the voting system, as long as
the probability is so low that we have far more
to worry about with the alternatives.
The wording problem is that criterion success or
failure depends on the wording, and the
interpretation as well. Or criterion failure
becomes meaningless. There was a purpose behind
the Majority Criterion, which is Majority Rule.
It is assumed that the first preference of a
majority must prevail, because this is implied by
Majority Rule. Except that a real majority in the
real world may choose to set aside its first
preference for a higher goal. And real majorities
do this quite well, when the system allows it to
be negotiated; currently we mostly see this in
small groups, but the principle is universal and
does not depend on scale, negotiation simply
becomes more difficult, we think, on a large scale. That problem can be fixed.
Approval satisfies the purposes of Majority Rule.
That's why it's offensive to insist that it fails
the Majority Criterion. If we return to the
original purpose, we see that it is more useful
to define the MC to refer to expressed votes, and
to require that the majority have a means to
express that preference, if they choose.
Again, we can look at standard deliberative
process. It's certainly possible that the
majority does not obtain its first preference,
but this *must* fail with an explicit acceptance
by a majority. I.e., the majority considers it
more important to gain a decision than to
absolute gain its first preference. Overall, we
must interpret this as the majority actually
preferring the result that they voted for. It was
just a simplified, possibly uninformed preference
that was the alleged "first preference."
In real, practical, non-political decision-making
systems, preferences are not fixed, they shift
during the process, they can reverse, especially when they are weak.
Why should politics be different?
>I know you dislike the term "vulnerable," but it seems to me that the
>criticism that Range is "vulnerable to strategic voting" is at least
>quite clear in what it refers to.
Once we defined it well, sure, but then the world
"vulnerable" is the use of a loaded term as a
term of art. Bad Idea. Misleads those who don't
know the field, and you can be sure that spin
doctors will use it that way. They won't provide
the definitions and restrictions.
> > > Ok. So Range ballots could permit the collection of
> > information needed
> > > to provide an "optimized outcome," if the
> > voters are accurate, which
> > > they won't be, because there is no specific
> > meaning to the ratings they
> > > can give.
> >
> > That's not true. It's just that there is not *one*
> > specific meaning. It's like Approval in that way.
>
>Ok. How far do you think this realization would get us? It seems to me
>that even if everyone agreed that Approval and Range allow multiple
>sincere and meaningful votes for a given set of sincere preferences,
>the criticisms would still be exactly the same. Only the terminology used
>might change.
No, some criticisms would disappear, because they
are *only* based on assumptions about the
importance of certain criteria failure. Being
strategy-free is of higher importance when
strategy involves preference reversal, than when
it merely means choosing how to express
preference strengths, but not violating
preference order. Being "vulnerable" implies
pathology, when reducing a result, in rare
circumstances, from ideal to almost-ideal, isn't pathological.
>Surely all this discussion isn't just to get people to change the terms
>that they use...?
It's to expose the hidden assumptions underneath
the terms, so that when these terms are used in a
misleading way, it can easily be seen, exposed.
> > Or we could just start with Bucklin. Simple. Allows the
> > expression of preferences (up to three in Duluth Bucklin).
> > Phases into Approval as a majority winner is not found with
> > a canvassed rank. Add in the next rank votes. Preferential
> > voting method that incorporates Range-like characteristics
> > and is not vulnerable to Center Squeeze. At least not as
> > seriously as IRV. We still see Center Squeeze if all the
> > voters really want Later-no-Harm and insist on it by not
> > ranking anyone else.
>
>I'd rather "start" with MCA (two rating levels plus the option to
>not rate at all) and stay there, as I think MCA is at least a little
>better than Approval.
How is it counted?
> > (I've proposed, yesterday, a hybrid IRV/Bucklin method
> > that allows voters to insist on LNH compliance with their
> > votes....)
>
>I'll have to find this as it's not clear to me how this would work.
I'd have to look back, I don't remember clearly at the moment.
> > > In this discussion we probably should not use the term
> > "strategy-free"
> > > except in cases where there are no meaningful
> > decisions.
> >
> > My point is that it was used that way, in peer-reviewed
> > publications, with a lot of agreement, re Approval.
>
>Did anyone use it that way who was not advocating the method?
I'm not sure. I do know that it wasn't just
Brams! And if Approval were "obviously
vulnerable," Brams would not have gotten away
with it. It took a process of redefining
strategic voting, which, I'm sure, including some
rapid response that the claim wasn't true, in
order to raise the idea that it was vulnerable.
I still don't see clear examples of what
"strategic voting" in Approval means, except
being Approval votes determined by the voter's
understanding of what candidates are the important ones.
> > > Well, none of this matters much as long as we use
> > consistent terms
> > > when having a discussion.
> >
> > Perhaps. But a discussion will also be read by many others.
> > It's tricky to use words with a specialized meaning when
> > a larger audience will read the text with generalized
> > meanings. Hence "accurate," which itself needs
> > definition, is far less a loaded term than
> > "sincere." Accurate raises the immediate question
> > "accurate to what?" And that's what a reader
> > would need to know.
>
>I want to note that I'm only interested in the terms used, in order
>to understand the underlying issues. I'm not interested in discussing
>what terms *ought* to be used.
I'm interested in, not only understanding issues,
but communicating the understandings.
> > The point is that the additional preference information
> > available in Range does not harm the outcome over not
> > allowing that information.
>
>However, this argument is only useful when you're talking to an Approval
>advocate.
Yet critics of Range use the alleged harm as an argument against Range.
>My feeling lately is that it might be better to arrange the incentives
>of a method so that a third candidate is likely to be able to gather
>enough support, as opposed to simply getting rid of all barriers to
>entry, which could tend to leave the two frontrunners unharmed.
The best way I know of is to allow the method to
terminate with majority failure. This, then, can
allow a third candidate who can make it into the
top two -- which can be better defined than
simply the top two in first preference votes --
the opportunity to convince the electorate in a
head-to-head contest with the other major
candidates that he or she is the best.
And that runoff tests a lot. If you can really
get the two best candidates into it, you've
eliminated a whole series of possible election
pathologies. I contend that we have two different
approaches to "best": Condorcet winner, on the
one hand, and expressed voter satisfaction
optimizer, on the other. If the method collects
both kinds of data, which is easy to arrange with
a Range ballot, we then can determine a result:
normally, large majority of elections, I believe,
the Condorcet winner is also the Range winner.
But it's the exceptions that are interesting, and
it's not difficult to test for the exceptions and
to consider these as ambiguous results, hence the
need for more voter attention to the election and to those specific candidates.
Could we agree that an ideal winner would be
either a Condorcet winner or a Range winner? Yes,
one could quibble about two candidates who beat
the Range winner pairwise, but this would be
extraordinarily rare; one of those two would have
higher Range summation, and, unless we want to
expand the runoff to three candidates, it would
seem to be overkill to go for more than one
member of the Condorcet cycle. But I'd be content
to use Schulze method, for example, to determine
the winner on the Condorcet side. We are talking
very rare that this wouldn't be moot. Normally,
if there is a candidate who beats the Range
winner, which is known to be relatively rare,
there would not be two or more. If we are using
sum-of-votes. Average Range is a little trickier.
There is no theoretical basis for Average Range,
it was a wild idea that sounded good to some
Range advocates, not to others. Unfortunately,
Warren is one who likes it. He is *not* politically sophisticated.
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list