minimal defense & SDSC (was Re: [EM] BeatpathWinner doesn't fail Markus' "SDSC".)
Steve Eppley
seppley at alumni.caltech.edu
Thu Feb 12 04:43:01 PST 2004
Markus wrote:
> Dear Mike,
> you wrote (4 Feb 2004):
> > Not only does Plurality pass your "SDSC",
-snip-
> If you mean Steve Eppley's "minimal defense" with "your 'SDSC'"
> then your example doesn't demonstrate a violation of this
> criterion since this majority of the voters doesn't rank
> candidate B "no higher than tied for bottom".
>
> Steve Eppley wrote (http://www.alumni.caltech.edu/~seppley):
> > Any ordering of the alternatives must be an admissible vote,
> > and if more than half of the voters rank y over x and x no
> > higher than tied for bottom, then x must not be elected.
Markus has taken an excerpt out of context, and in this
case it is misleading. (Perhaps I should search my election-
methods-list folder to see how often my writing has been
misrepresented.) Here's more of what I actually posted at
the webpage Markus cited, which shows how Markus distorted
my definition:
minimal defense: If more than half of the voters prefer
alternative y over alternative x, then that majority
must have some way of voting that ensures x will not
be elected and does not require any of them to rank y
equal to or over any alternatives preferred over y.
(Another wording is nearly equivalent: Any ordering
of the alternatives must be an admissible vote, and
if more than half of the voters rank y over x and
x no higher than tied for bottom, then x must not
be elected. This criterion, in particular the first
wording, is promoted by Mike Ossipoff under the name
Strong Defensive Strategy Criterion. -snip- )
The definitions in that "table of contents" webpage have
been made brief and simple for the sake of laymen who might
read the page. The complete definition of minimal defense
is in a document two clicks away from that page. (Click on
"minimal defense" then click on "Strategic Indifference".)
Minimal Defense: For all subsets X of the alternatives,
if there exists an alternative y that more than half
the voters prefer over every alternative in X,
then there must exist a set of voting strategies
for that majority that ensures no alternative in X
will be elected and does not require any of them to
misrepresent any preferences except possibly lowering
alternatives in X.
I should add a clause to strengthen that:
"... and without having to lower any alternative in X
below a tie for bottom with their least-preferred
alternative(s)."
In addition to the obvious reduction of preference
misrepresentation implied by this clause, I seem to recall
from years ago that the clause serves to ensure a group
strategy equilibrium (much more desirable than a Nash
equilibrium) by preventing the creation of new strategic
reversal opportunities that could arise if X is lowered
below other alternatives. It may be unclear when
organizing the defensive strategy how popular the other
candidates will be on election day. For instance, if some
supporters of y downrank x below z (rather than tied for
bottom with z) to deter suporters of x from attempting a
reversal strategy (x over z over y), then supporters of z
who prefer z over y over x may be given an opportunity to
elect z by reversing x over y.
It was near-accidental that I noticed Markus' message. I
haven't read the previous messages in the thread, but it's
clear from the subject line that Mike was referring to some
(re)definition of SDSC allegedly posted by Markus, not to a
definition posted by me.
---Steve (Steve Eppley seppley at alumni.caltech.edu)
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list