[EM] axioms for lotteries
Forest Simmons
simmonfo at up.edu
Fri Feb 25 15:59:41 PST 2005
Let P represent the set of candidates that have a positive probability of
winning, i.e. P is the support of the winning lottery. What if we require
the following?
1. The set P cannot be empty.
2. Any candidate that has more approval than some member of P must also be
a member of P.
3. Any candidate that beats some member of P pairwise must also be a
member of P.
>From these conditions it would follow that the Smith set is contained in
P, and every candidate that is more approved than some member of the Smith
set would also be a member of P.
In particular, the Approval winner is a member of P, as is the CW if there
is one.
Hereafter assume that P is the smallest set that satisfies the three
conditions above.
If P is a singleton, then its only member is both the CW and the Approval
winner, and according to the unique lottery based on P, this
Approval/Condorcet candidate wins the lottery with 100 percent certainty.
In general (i.e. even if P is not a singleton), if W wins and the
supporters of some other candidate C complain, how can the supporters of W
respond?
Well, they can say that there is a sequence of candidates W=C1, C2, ...
Ck=C, such that each candidate in the sequence beats the next either
pairwise or approval-wise.
Furthermore, if there is a similar sequence from C to W, then C also had a
positive chance of winning but just didn't have the luck of the draw.
It seems to me that this is a reasonable way to answer loser complaints.
It remains to be seen how probabilities should be assigned to the members
of P in such a way that monotonicity and clone independence are satisfied,
as well as the all important discouragement of insincere order reversals.
Uniform probability on P would violate clone independence because
large clone sets would have a disproportionate share of the probability
compared to small ones.
Perhaps random ballot restricted to the members of P would be the way to
go.
Alternately, one could construct the beat clone hierarchy for P, and
assign the probabilities accordingly, but this is potentially messy.
One simple example:
55 A>B>>C
45 C>B>>A
We get P={A,B} since A beats B pairwise, but B has more approval than A.
[Candidate C has no beat path of any kind to either member of P.]
If we assign probabilities according to random ballot restricted to P,
then the probabilities for A and B are .55 and .45, respectively.
Next time if the first faction thinks that it still has a solid majority
(and still prefers A to B), they will probably vote A>>B>C. If so, then A
will become the unique member of P, thereby winning the lottery with
certainty.
A majority favorite always has a positive probability of winning, and as
we see in the above example, a persistent majority favorite will
eventually win with certainty.
Forest
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list