[EM] Condorcet Strategy Reply, part 1 (of 3)
MIKE OSSIPOFF
nkklrp at hotmail.com
Fri May 28 22:33:01 PDT 2004
James--
You wrote:
For public elections, I'm recommending the following procedure.
1. Ranked vote. Pairwise tally. If there is a Condorcet winner, they take
office.
2. If there is no Condorcet winner, non-members of the Schwartz set...
I reply:
In public elections, where pairwise ties are vanishingly rare, the Schwartz
set is the same as the Smith set. And the Smith set is a lot briefer and
simpler to define. So, for public election proposals, I suggest changing
"Schwartz set" to "Smith set".
You continued:
...are
eliminated from further consideration.
I reply:
I repeat here my suggestion that there's no reason to hold a 2nd balloting
for order-reversal protection unless the circular tie has all majority
defeats. That's because a circular tie won by a majority-beaten candidate
must have all majority defeats in the circular tie.
You continued:
In addition, there is a period of
time between votes where any member of the Schwartz set has the option of
dropping out of the race and removing their name from the second ballot.
3. A second ranked vote takes place. The Condorcet winner or completed
winner of the second vote takes office.
I reply:
Aside from my suggestion to only hold the 2nd balloting if the circular tie
is all majority-beaten, I don't have any objections to that proposal. As you
know, I prefer Approval for the 2nd balloting, but either Approval or
Condorcet would be fine for the 2nd balloting. Others too have told me that
they'd prefer Condorcet to Approval for the 2nd balloting.
You continued:
At this point I think that the problem is very serious, easily serious
enough to justify another balloting if such a second balloting would help,
and possibly serious enough to render single-balloting Condorcet
critically unreliable as a voting method.
I reply:
...unreliable compared to what? IRV will jump to extremes because of its own
idiosyncracy. Condorcet will jump to an extreme only if someone sucessfully
uses the risky offensive order-reversal strategy. Purality can fail to elect
a CW if sufficiently many people don't bury their favorite.
Two main differences between Condorcet and IRV or Plurality:
1. IRV & Plurality spontaneously let an extreme beat the CW, unless
defensive strategy is knowledgably used. That happens in Condorcet only if
the risky offensive order-reversal strategy is successfully used.
2. In all of these methods the CW can be protected by defensive strategy. In
Condorcet that defensive strategy is equal ranking, or defensive truncation
which, though not electing the CW, will deter offensive order-reversal. In
IRV & Plurality, that defensive strategy requires burying one's favorite.
These are things that I've been telling you all along, but you continue to
speak of Condorcet's strategy problem in a vacuum, as if Condorcet were the
only method with a strategy problem. Maybe you'll just keep on repeating
your claims without replying to these objections to them, but, if so, I just
want everyone to know that that's what you're doing. You're repeating
without listening.
All 3 methods, Condorcet, IRV, & Plurailty, can elect an extreme candidate
instead of the CW. But that's where the similarity ends. These 3 methods
differ in the two numbered ways that I described above. Of course they also
differ in their strategy criteria compliances, the strategy guarantees that
they offer.
You continued:
I'm not entirely sure about
this, but that's the way it seems to me now. As for whether a second
balloting would significantly mitigate this problem, I'm not sure, but I
*hope* so.
I reply:
A 2nd balloting would help. As would all the strategy enhancements that I
described here.
You continued:
(Actually there is also a third, namely: is there a way of mitigating the
strategy problem that is both easier (i.e. one ballot) and more
effective
I reply:
James, I posted a list of strategy enhancements for 1-balloting Condorcet
that reduce its aready relatively minor strategy problem.
You're requiring perfection from Condorcet. You remind me of that scene from
_How I Won the War_, in which the sergeant is inspecting the squad, out in
the desert. He walks by the row of assembled soldiers. One of them is
wearing a clown-suit, and is dyed (maybe blue, green or red) from head to
toe. The sergeant walks by the clown, and then stops at the next man, and
says "You're out of uniform! You don't have collar-stays!".
No, you won't find perfection in any voting system. But if you compare
Condorcet's strategy to that of other voting systems, instead of comparing
it to perfection, you'll find that the others are worse.
You continued:
Many people seem to disagree with me on one or both of these questions...
let's see if we can get a meaningful and productive discussion going on
the topic. Myself, I'm open-minded about the issue, and I hope that you
can be open-minded as well.
I reply:
That's big of you. You can start being open-minded by looking at Condorcet's
strategy in comparison to the strategies of other voting sytsems, instead of
expecting it to meet standards that the other methods fail worse than
Condrocet does.
A supporter of the CW, wanting to deter offensive order-reversal strategy
against his candidate, doesn't have to know who is going to attempt
offensive order-reversal, or even if anyone is going to. All s/he has to do
is not rank anyone except hir candidate. Then, any offensive order-reversal
against that candidate will backfire.
You complain later in your posting that s/he can't know that hir candidate
is CW, and that hir truncation could take hir support away from the real CW.
Yes, James, that's the whole problem, with all the methods' strategy
situation: We don't have perfect information. I said that in my previous
posting. I find that I'm repeating these same answers, in reply to
successive long postings of yours, because, in those long postings, you just
repeat your claims, quite oblivious to the fact that they've just been
answered.
As I said before, the difference is in 1) what it takes to bring that
strategy situation about; and 2) What it takes to protect the CW, or to
protect majority rule. By both of those 2 standards, Condorcet does much
better than IRV or Pluraity. Approval beats IRV & Plurality by the 2nd
standard.
You continued:
Sincere preferences
27: A>B
25: B>A
24: C>A
24: C>B
Pairwise comparisons
A:B = 51 : 49
A:C = 52 : 48
B:C = 52 : 48
A is a Condorcet winner. But if just a fraction of the B voters reverse
their preferences, they can steal the election for B.
27: A>B
21: B>A
4: B>C
24: C>A
24: C>B
Pairwise comparisons
A:B = 51 : 49
A:C = 48 : 52
B:C = 52 : 48
I reply:
You originally brought up this co-operation/defection dilemma in connection
with Approval. I answered it recently on EM, bringing it up as a Condorcet
problem, but also discussing it in terms of Approval.
I guess it's necessary to repeat some of that: That's IRV's shining example.
For the A & B voters.
If A or B is taken advantage of by the other, it isn't a majority rule
violation. Though strategy problems are undesirable, we should measure them
for comparison. In contrast, IRV's failure is often a majority rule problem.
You're looking at it from the point of view of the mutual majority, the
{A,B} voters. What about the C voters in IRV? Say they prefer one of {A,B}
to the other. Say they can pretty well tell that C can't win, because the A
& B voters are a mutual majority. That means that the C voters gain nothing
by sincerely voting C 1st in IRV. Their best strategy is to vote their {A,B}
favorite in 1st place, burying their favorite.
So what, you might say, C can't win, and shouldn't be able to. Sure, but
what if they're mistaken in their belief that they should use
favorite-burial compromise strategy? That's the whole problem, you know,
when voters don't have complete information, and mis-estimate, and either
give away the election or fail to protect a needed compromise. You talk of
Condorcet voters who don't have perfect information. What about those C
voters in IRV who don't have compelte information.
So every mutual majorilty example of the kind that you use as a Condorcet or
Approval co-operation/defection dilemma is also an IRV failure example for
WDSC & FBC, two criteria met by Approval and by all the wv versions.
You exaggerate the benefit of defection: It will result in the loss of the
support that you'll need from your victims in the next election. In the next
election, you can't expect them to co-operate again. If anyone co-operates
then it will be you. I mentioned the Tit-For-Tat strategy in my previouis
posting. The voters who have been victimized by defection might refuse to
co-operate with their victimizers ever again, or they might just use TFT,
whereby they copy the most recent strategy of the other "player".
Co-operation/defection games aren't the hopeless disaster that you might
think they are.
Aside from that, since we're now discussing Condorcet, the ATLO option would
solve your co-operation/defection dillema: A voters or B voters rank
sincerely, but apply ATLO below their favorite. If no one defects, either A
or B wins, depending on which have more voters. If one defects, making a
strategic circular tie, then the circular tie triggers ATLO, and the
co-operating side withdraws its support for the defecting side, and C wins.
Both side know that will happen if they defect. Neither side defects.
I'm gonig to stop and mail this now. I'm posting this reply in 3 parts,
because last time my reply was so long that it almost didn't post, and its
posting was delayed because of its length. Part 2 will be along tonight or
tomorrow.
Mike Ossipoff
_________________________________________________________________
FREE pop-up blocking with the new MSN Toolbar get it now!
http://toolbar.msn.click-url.com/go/onm00200415ave/direct/01/
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list