[EM] Does anyone know who this person is?
Kristofer Munsterhjelm
km_elmet at t-online.de
Tue Oct 26 08:24:37 PDT 2021
On 10/25/21 2:35 AM, fdpk69p6uq at snkmail.com wrote:
> Why does their identity matter? Discuss the facts, not ad hominems.
>
> Also, I'm surprised and a bit saddened that you haven't come around to
> cardinal systems yet. :/
>
> The goal of democracy is to elect the candidate who best represents the
> will of the voters. My near-indifference between two candidates
> shouldn't arbitrarily be given the same weight as your strong preference
> between them.
Let me make a ranked voting advocate (ordinalist?) argument here. I'll
be referring to "simple cardinal methods", by which I mean things like
Range, and not so much things that I'm fumbling towards in my utility posts.
Cardinal supporters tend to use two arguments to argue for the
superiority of cardinal methods over ordinal ones.
The first is that cardinal methods support strength of preference; and
the second is that, because they pass FBC (and IIA), they inherently are
more robust to strategy.
My response to these are, much abbreviated, that first, the "strength of
preference" that these methods gather is probably ambiguous, and if it
weren't, it would come with significant disadvantages.
And second, that the methods' IIA and FBC compliance take a form that
shoves what used to be tactical voting into a mush that's kind of
honest, kind of not; and that once that's made clear, it's obvious that
the methods no longer achieve the impossible. But because it doesn't
look like ranked voting strategy, cardinal advocates can shift between a
position that the methods permit everybody to vote "honestly" (an easy
position) and that the methods are strategy-proof (a hard, incorrect
position).
-
So for the first point, let's use Range as the standard cardinal method.
Range asks for a set of ratings that are intended to represent utility,
so that your rating is proportional to the utility you achieve from
seeing this candidate elected. That's what's being demonstrated in
examples like the pizza election: that the meat eaters show that their
utility from getting mushroom pizza is not that far off from the utility
of getting pepperoni, so that the method elects the pizza that satisfies
all.
But here's a problem. I can't know that my scale is calibrated the same
way as yours. In philosophy, this is known as the problem of
incommensurability. Suppose I happen to feel more pleasure (and pain)
than you, but due to growing up in the same society as you, I mistakenly
appear to use the same scale as you. It's then quite hard to know that
when I say 6/10 I mean what you would consider twice as good as that.
At first it would seem, though, that Range has dodged a bullet. Because
if utility were directly comparable on an absolute scale, then there
might exist "pleasure wizards"[1] who obtain so much utility from a
choice that they effectively become dictators. By insisting on a 0-1
scale (in its continuous version), Range limits the power any one voter
has and so enforces a weak type of one man, one vote. It is what I
called a type three method - voters might voluntarily decide to forego
some of their power to make the outcome better for others (again, as in
the pizza election).
But the problem with this is that Range supposes that there's a common
scale where there isn't. As a consequence, the concept of just what is a
honest vote becomes blurred. E.g. suppose that I consider the sure
election of Y to be equally good as a 50-50 shot of either X or Z
winning. Do I rate X 1, Y 0.5, and Z 0? Or do I rate X 0.5, Y 0.25, and
Z 0? Because there's no way to answer that question (unless it somehow
becomes possible to get at utility information), there's more than one
honest vote, and a honest voter is faced with the burden of having to
decide *which one*. (It is assumed that voters will answer the question
by normalizing[2], but this leads to strategy problems which I'll get to.)
My attempts to generalize STAR came from asking "what if we want to be
truly honest about what information it makes sense to ask of voters,
while respecting OMOV?". Well, we could ask the voters about preferences
over lotteries (as the 50-50 vs certainty example above). Doing so, the
method acknowledges the ambiguity of comparing utility. Perhaps there's
more we can do - e.g. by following MJ's reasoning of a common standard,
or by separating "worse than nothing happening" events from "better than
nothing happening" ones.
But all of this is better than just saying "it means what you want it to
mean", and then sweeping the resulting ambiguity in honest voters under
the carpet.
-
As for the point that e.g. Range is superior to ordinal methods because
Range passes IIA and the ordinal ones don't, I always feel like that's a
bit of a sleight of hand. To explain, let's divide the ballot types into
three:
1. The highest information honest ballot (ranking candidates in order of
preference, reporting relative utility values in Range).
2. Other honest ballots: some monotone transformation of this.
3. Tactical/dishonest ballots (order reversal).
Ranked methods have a very obvious category one, and going for some
category two ballot instead (e.g. equal rank or truncation) doesn't
usually produce much harm. Cardinal methods like Range replaces most of
category three with category two because they pass FBC and IIA.
As I've argued above, there's not really a category one for Range
because it asks for more than the voter can provide. And we know from
Gibbard's theorem that no deterministic voting method (cardinal or
ordinal) is entirely free of strategy. So both categories one and three
collapse into category two in Range: the former because there's no one
honest ballot, and the latter because order-reversal isn't necessary
(the famous FBC compliance, but it's actually stronger than just FBC).
So, in ranked voting methods, voting strategy consists of choosing an
appropriate category three ballot. In methods like Range, it consists of
choosing an appropriate category two ballot.
But here's the problem: having a clearly defined category one and a
narrow category two means that a voter who values honesty *as such* can
just choose the one honest ballot and then go home without regrets. But
in Range, because "every ballot is honest", he has to carefully
deliberate *which* honest vote to choose. And if he chooses wrong (e.g.
in a Burr dilemma), he'll sure come to regret it.
That kind of peril should only exist, IMHO, for voters who decide to
play rough by choosing a category three ballot.
And thus the sleight of hand: in a ranked method, "honest" means more or
less category one[3]. So cardinal voting proponents can say "oh, but our
category three is empty because of FBC!", but all they're really doing
is shifting the Gibbard-mandated instrumental voting from category three
over to category two. This lets them say "you can just vote honestly",
thus giving the impression there's no risk in Range. But it's actually
the other way around: it's not only determined strategic voters who may
regret the strategy they chose, but also honest voters who just want to
vote honestly and go home.
This also poisons the value of IIA. If IIA is to be practically
meaningful, it must mean that the outcome doesn't change when a
candidate who didn't win drops out. But if every voter is deliberating
which type-two ballot to go for, the ballots may change even if the
sentiment doesn't.
In other words: if enough voters normalize in Approval, then Approval's
IIA compliance isn't worth much at all in practice. E.g. first round
ballots:
25: A>B>>C
40: B>C>>A
35: C>A>>B
The Approval winner is C.
But now let A drop out, and the voters renormalize (as Warren suggests
everybody would):
25: B>>C
40: B>>C
35: C>>B
and then B wins, so even though Approval passes IIA de jure, it looks
rather different de facto. Telling the voters to perform a particular
algorithm on their ballots before submitting them, and then claiming the
inputs to the method satisfies IIA, doesn't mean the method plus the
manual algorithm passes IIA!
So the problem, in summing up, is that there's too much vagueness to
hide subtleties in. Cardinal methods measure utility (but they don't, so
what do they measure?). Cardinal methods let you vote honestly (but
honest doesn't mean the same thing anymore). Cardinal methods pass IIA
and FBC (but it does them much less good than ranked methods). Bayesian
regret evaluations show Range as superior to ranked methods (but
questionable assumptions about voter strategy may invalidate the results).
It's better to be honest about the limitations that exist. If we can
only get lottery information, then the method should reflect that. If we
can get more, then the method should show how we can get it. That way,
there won't be anything up its sleeve.
-km
[1]
https://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195189254.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780195189254-e-020
or, if you're more in a funny mood,
https://www.smbc-comics.com/comic/2012-04-03 :-)
[2] E.g. Warren Smith says voters will do so because they're not
"strategic idiots", and that voters who don't normalize in a
two-candidate election are simply "idiots".
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2006-December/084357.html
and
http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2007-January/084662.html
respectively.
[3] There's a caveat here because equal-rank/truncation seem to be in
category two, and so a response to this reasoning would be "ranked
ballots have category two too!". But there's very little regret in
choosing category one instead of two, in practice. However, some ranked
methods that pass FBC do so by making equal-rank stronger than strict
ranking, and those reintroduce the problem.
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list