[EM] Losing Votes (equal-ranking whole)

C.Benham cbenham at adam.com.au
Sat Jun 1 05:46:26 PDT 2019


Jim,

Yes.

Chris Benham

On 1/06/2019 9:45 pm, Faran, James wrote:
> 51 A>B>C>D
> 49 B>C>D>A
>
> Is A a better choice than B?
>
> 1. Yes. Plurality demands it. Moreover, B beats C and D on all 
> ballots, so C and D can be ignored and the pairwise race is all that's 
> left.
>
> 2. No. A is ranked bottom on 49% of ballots, B ranked at least second 
> on 100%, top on almost half.
>
> Are C and D Irrelevant Alternatives?
>
> Jim Faran
>
> On Jun 1, 2019 5:28 AM, "C.Benham" <cbenham at adam.com.au> wrote:
>
> Toby,
>
> I didn't coin the Plurality criterion, and I do somewhat prefer your 
> suggested alternative wording. To take account of equal-top ranking being
> allowed, I would specify the fractional interpretation of "number of 
> ballots ranking A as the first preference".  The original coiner of 
> the criterion
> was operating on the assumption that no  equal-ranking would be 
> allowed (except at the bottom implied by truncation which would be 
> allowed)
> and perhaps also that no-one would needlessly mark a candidate 
> strictly bottom when they could just truncate.
>
> I think in part the criterion is tailor-made for voters accustomed to 
> and content with plurality voting, and after some new election on ballots
> that allow voters to rank the candidates is used, they want to know 
> why B won while their favourite candidate A was voted (alone) in first 
> place
> on more ballots than B was voted above bottom. And I like the 
> criterion because I agree that there can't be a good enough answer.
>
> A standard  (and possible criterion) I like says that if  A both 
> positionally dominates and pairwise beats B then B can't win. That 
> implies Plurality.
>
> 35: A
> 10: A=B
> 30: B>C
> 25: C
>
> Here no ballots vote A or B below equal-top. A has more top (or first) 
> place votes than B so positionally dominates and pairwise beats B.
> Do you think B is an acceptable winner?
>
> Chris Benham
>
>
>
> On 29/05/2019 10:37 pm, Toby Pereira wrote:
>> I don't have a definite answer to the question of equally ranked 
>> ballots, and to me I suppose it's still an open question exactly what 
>> the best way forwards is, even if you make a good argument against 
>> margins.
>>
>> I don't have an example where the plurality criterion bars from 
>> winning the candidate that I think should have won. Looking at the 
>> definition on the Wikipedia: "If the number of ballots ranking A as 
>> the first preference is greater than the number of ballots on which 
>> another candidate B is given any preference, then A's probability of 
>> winning must be no less than B's.", it's more that I would disagree 
>> with the terminology "given any preference."
>>
>> If the definition was "If the number of ballots ranking A as the 
>> first preference is greater than the number of ballots on which 
>> another candidate B is ranked anything other than last or joint last 
>> (either explicitly or through implication on a truncated ballot), 
>> then A's probability of winning must be no less than B's." then I'd 
>> be less critical of it. I think the way it's worded implies an 
>> approval cut-off even if in practice it makes no difference.
>>
>> Toby
>>
>>
>> ------------------------------------------------------------------------
>> *From:* C.Benham <cbenham at adam.com.au>
>> *To:* Toby Pereira <tdp201b at yahoo.co.uk>; "cbenham at adam.com.au" 
>> <cbenham at adam.com.au>; "election-methods at lists.electorama.com" 
>> <election-methods at lists.electorama.com>
>> *Sent:* Sunday, 26 May 2019, 20:19
>> *Subject:* Re: [EM] Losing Votes (equal-ranking whole)
>>
>> Toby,
>>
>> If you try to give that calculator a truncated ballot it will just 
>> turn it into the sort of ballot you like.
>>
>> How do you think equally-ranked ballots should be counted in a 
>> pairwise comparison?  A half-vote to
>> each or zero to both?
>>
>> So you can't actually point to any election example where the 
>> Plurality criterion bars from winning the candidate
>> that you think should have won?
>> 46: A
>> 44: B>C
>> 10: C
>> Returning to this, are you happy with B winning?  And if not, why not?
>>
>> Chris Benham
>>
>> On 27/05/2019 3:38 am, Toby Pereira wrote:
>> By unranked candidates, I meant the ones that had not had any sort of 
>> "vote" - the ones not explicitly listed by the voter. If there are 
>> three candidates in an election, A, B, and C, I might like A but 
>> absolutely hate the others. My vote might simply be:
>>
>> A
>>
>> On the other hand, while I might still absolutely hate B and C, I 
>> might still hate C more. So my vote might be:
>>
>> A>B
>>
>> But just because I have ranked B on my ballot, this should not be 
>> taken as any sort of endorsement of B or a vote "for" B.
>>
>> My vote could also be:
>>
>> A>B>C
>>
>> Does adding C on the end mean that I have in some sense voted for C? 
>> I don't think there would actually be any methods where adding C on 
>> the end would have any effect on how the winner is calculated, but 
>> the plurality criterion would presumably in theory find it acceptable 
>> to do so.
>>
>> But this is more a philosophical objection to the assumptions 
>> implicit in the plurality criterion than an an objection to the 
>> results that a method obeying the criterion would produce in 
>> practice. But anyway, I put my thoughts about the plurality criterion 
>> a while ago (as did Juho) here: 
>> http://election-methods.5485.n7.nabble.com/EM-Fwd-Ordering-defeats-in-Minimax-td34236.html#a34247
>>
>> But anyway, thank you for the link to the calculator.
>>
>> Toby
>>
>>
>>
>>
>> ------------------------------------------------------------------------
>> *From:* Chris Benham <cbenhamau at yahoo.com.au> 
>> <mailto:cbenhamau at yahoo.com.au>
>> *To:* "tdp201b at yahoo.co.uk" <mailto:tdp201b at yahoo.co.uk> 
>> <tdp201b at yahoo.co.uk> <mailto:tdp201b at yahoo.co.uk>; 
>> "cbenham at adam.com.au" <mailto:cbenham at adam.com.au> 
>> <cbenham at adam.com.au> <mailto:cbenham at adam.com.au>; 
>> "election-methods at lists.electorama.com" 
>> <mailto:election-methods at lists.electorama.com> 
>> <election-methods at lists.electorama.com> 
>> <mailto:election-methods at lists.electorama.com>
>> *Sent:* Sunday, 26 May 2019, 18:08
>> *Subject:* Re: [EM] Losing Votes (equal-ranking whole)
>>
>> Toby,
>>
>> You would like this old online ranked-ballot voting calculator:
>>
>> https://www.cse.wustl.edu/~legrand/rbvote/calc.html
>>
>> What do you think are the "false premises" that the Plurality 
>> criterion is based on??? It was coined with the assumption
>> that voters could only strictly rank from the top however many 
>> candidates they wish, and those not truncated had in
>> some sense been "voted for". It says that if A has more first-place 
>> votes than B has any sort of votes then B can't win.
>> No explicit mention of "unranked candidates".
>>
>> (Adapting it to ballots that allow equal-ranking at the top,?? "first 
>> preferences" refers to first-preference score on the
>> ballots symmetrically completed, at least at the top, ballots).
>> To sensibly claim that it is a "mistake" for an algorithm to do (or 
>> apparently "assume") something, I think you need to
>> point to something wrong with an actual result of it doing so.
>>
>> My answer to your question is no.
>> Chris Benham
>>
>>
>> On 27/05/2019 1:04 am, Toby Pereira wrote:
>> I think it's a mistake to assume some sort of approval of a ranked 
>> candidate. If it's not explicitly part of a method then you should 
>> not infer it. As far as I'm concerned:
>>
>> 46: A
>> 44: B>C
>> 10: C
>>
>> Is the same as:
>>
>> 46: A>B=C
>> 44: B>C>A
>> 10: C>A=B
>>
>> Presented with these ballots, does this change who you think the 
>> winner should be?
>>
>> This isn't a defence of margins by me or an argument against anything 
>> else in your post, but I think the plurality criterion, by talking 
>> about unranked candidates, is based on false premises.
>>
>> Toby
>>
>>     On Sat, 25 May 2019 at 15:31, C.Benham
>>     <cbenham at adam.com.au> <mailto:cbenham at adam.com.au> wrote:
>>     There are several Condorcet algorithms that decide the winner by
>>     weighing "defeat strengths" and they
>>     are all equivalent to MinMax when there are no more than 3
>>     candidates.
>>
>>     The ones I have in mind that are equal or very nearly equal in
>>     merit are
>>     River, Schulze, Ranked Pairs, Smith//MinMax.
>>     In public political elections they are very very unlikely to give
>>     different winners. River and Smith//MinMax seem to me
>>     to be the easiest to understand and explain and use. The other
>>     two are
>>     perhaps a bit more elegant and have their
>>     enthusiastic supporters.
>>
>>     This is to make the case that measuring pairwise defeat strength
>>     by the
>>     number of votes on the losing side with above-bottom
>>     equal-ranking contributing a whole vote to each side (and
>>     otherwise as
>>     with normal Winning Votes) is much better than either
>>     Winning Votes or Margins.
>>
>>     The case for Losing Votes(erw) against Margins is that it (in common
>>     with WV) it meets the Plurality criterion and the Non-Drastic
>>     Defense criterion.
>>
>>     The case for Losing Votes(erw) against Winning Votes is that it
>>     meets
>>     the Chicken Dilemma criterion and that is much less likely
>>     to fail to elect a positionally dominant uncovered candidate. (I
>>     don't
>>     see how it can fail to elect such a candidate in the 3-candidate
>>     case.)
>>
>>     For those who think that Margins might be acceptable:
>>
>>     46: A
>>     44: B>C
>>     10: C
>>
>>     A>B 46-44 (margin=2), B>C 44-10 (margin=34), C>A 54-46 (margin=8).
>>
>>     Using Losing Votes (erw) as the measure of defeat strength, the
>>     weakest
>>     defeat is the one with the most votes on the losing side.
>>     That is the C>A defeat so MinMax drops that and A wins.
>>     Conversely the
>>     strongest defeat is the one with the fewest votes on the
>>     losing side. That is the B>C defeat so River and Ranked Pairs lock
>>     that. The second strongest is the A>B defeat so those methods
>>     also lock that. All but one candidate has been thereby
>>     disqualified so B
>>     wins, or we ignore the third pairwise defeat because that
>>     makes a cycle, so give a final order A>B>C and A wins.
>>
>>     To meet both of the Plurality criterion and the Chicken Dilemma
>>     criterion A must win.
>>
>>     Winning Votes elects C, violating Chicken Dilemma (which it has
>>     to do to
>>     meet the previously fashionable Minimal Defense criterion).
>>
>>     Margins elects B. This fails the Plurality criterion because A
>>     has more
>>     exclusive first-place votes than B has any sort of above-bottom
>>     votes. It is also an egregious and outrageous failure of
>>     Later-no-Help
>>     (assuming that if all the ballots just vote for one candidate we
>>     elect the plurality winner).
>>
>>     To anyone who is remotely positionally or strategically minded or
>>     has
>>     any common sense and isn't blind to everything except the
>>     Margins pairwise matrix, B is clearly the weakest candidate and a
>>     completely unacceptable winner.
>>
>>     35: A
>>     10: A=B
>>     30: B>C
>>     25: C
>>
>>     A>B 45-40 (erw, "normally" 35-30, margin=5), B>C 40-25 (margin=15),
>>     C>A 55-45 (margin=10).
>>
>>     Voted at least equal-top (or Top Ratings) scores: A45, B40, C25.
>>     Voted above bottom (or Approval) scores:  A45,  B40, C55
>>
>>     An old Kevin Venzke example. B is neither the most top-rated
>>     candidate
>>     or the most approved candidate and is
>>     pairwise-beaten and positionally dominated by A (the most top-rated).
>>
>>     Winning Votes and Margins both elect the clearly weakest
>>     candidate, B.
>>     Losing Votes(erw) elects A.
>>
>>     For those who prefer to have a method comply with Minimal Defense
>>     (which
>>     says that if on more than half the ballots
>>     C is voted above A and A no higher than equal-bottom then A can't
>>     win)
>>     rather than Chicken Dilemma another method
>>     I prefer to WV is Smith//Approval which here elects C.
>>
>>     25: A>B
>>     26: B>C
>>     23: C>A
>>     26: C
>>
>>     C>A 75-25 (margin=50), A>B 48-26 (margin=22), B>C 51-49 (margin=2).
>>
>>     Voted at least equal-top (or Top Ratings) scores: C49, B26, A25.
>>     Voted above bottom (or Approval) scores:  C75, B51, A48.
>>
>>     C is an overwhelmingly positionally dominant uncovered candidate.
>>     Margins and Losing Votes elect C.
>>     WV and IRV elect B.
>>
>>     Now say we change 4 of the 26 C ballots to A>C, thereby making C
>>     a bit
>>     weaker.
>>
>>     25: A>B
>>     26: B>C
>>     23: C>A
>>     22: C
>>     04: A>C
>>
>>     C>A 71-29 (margin=42), A>B 52-26 (margin=26), B>C 51-49 (margin=2).
>>
>>     Voted at least equal-top (or Top Ratings) scores: C45, B26, A29.
>>     Voted above bottom (or Approval) scores:  C75, B51, A52.
>>
>>
>>     The weakening of C has caused WV and IRV to change from B to C, now
>>     agreeing with LV and Margins.
>>     Assuming the change was from sincere to insincere, those very lucky
>>     and/or very well informed 4 voters
>>     have pulled off a Push-over strategy.
>>
>>     This is a failure of Mono-raise-delete (more obvious if we
>>     reverse the
>>     order of the two situations), which
>>     is one of Woodall's mononicity criteria that he says is incompatible
>>     with Condorcet.
>>
>>     Nonetheless in this case C is still the positionally dominant
>>     uncovered
>>     candidate and Losing Votes (erw)
>>     and Margins both still elect C.
>>
>>     Steve Eppley's old example to illustrate (I think his) Non-Drastic
>>     Defense criterion, which says that if
>>     on more than half the ballots B is voted no lower than equal-top and
>>     above A then A can't win.
>>
>>     46: A>C (sincere may be A>B)
>>     10: B>A
>>     10: B>C
>>     34: C=B (the "defenders", sincere may be C>B)
>>
>>     B>A 54-46 (m=8), A>C 56-44 (m=12), C>B (80-54 erw, "normally"
>>     46-20, m=26).
>>
>>     Voted at least equal-top (or Top Ratings) scores: B54, A46, C34.
>>     Voted above bottom (or Approval) scores:  B54, A56, C90.
>>
>>     B is the only candidate top-rated on more than half the ballots.
>>     More
>>     than half the voters voted B
>>     above A and B not lower than equal-top. Margins and Losing Votes
>>     without my recommended
>>     "above-bottom equal-ranking whole" bit elect A, violating the
>>     Non-Drastic Defense criterion.
>>
>>     Losing Votes (erw) and WV elect B.
>>
>>     If anyone has some counter-examples where they think that Winning
>>     Votes
>>     does better than
>>     Losing Votes (erw), I'd be interested in seeing them.
>>
>>     Chris Benham
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>     ----
>>     Election-Methods mailing list - see https://electorama.com/em
>>     <https://electorama.com/em>for list info
>>
>>
>> <http://www.avg.com/email-signature?utm_medium=email&utm_source=link&utm_campaign=sig-email&utm_content=emailclient> 
>> 	Virus-free. www.avg.com 
>> <http://www.avg.com/email-signature?utm_medium=email&utm_source=link&utm_campaign=sig-email&utm_content=emailclient> 
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>


---
This email has been checked for viruses by AVG.
https://www.avg.com
-------------- next part --------------
An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
URL: <http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/attachments/20190601/8c159ac1/attachment-0001.html>


More information about the Election-Methods mailing list