[EM] FairVote comment on Burlington dumping IRV

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax abd at lomaxdesign.com
Thu Jul 4 18:16:34 PDT 2013


At 11:38 AM 7/4/2013, Jameson Quinn wrote:
>OK. I think we can work this out. Before I make more arguments, I'm 
>going to try to explain the disagreements as I see them, and ask you 
>more about what you're saying.
>
>A. MAV vs. ER-Bucklin (ERB, though we should probably find a better 
>name at some point). That is, completion using above-median, or 
>completion using median-or-above.
>
>I don't see a huge difference here. I think MAV is slightly better 
>because of the chicken dilemma, but it's possible that that regular 
>voters would see ERB as simpler by a big enough margin to make it 
>worth supporting instead. I'm probably not a good judge of that 
>because my mathy brain tends to see them as exactly symmetrical.
>
>I think you're beginning to understand my point about symmetry. Your 
>view is that ERB is better because of apparent simplicity (empirical 
>question about voters; we could find agreement here with more 
>evidence) and also because of some Deep Principle of counting all 
>the votes which I don't understand (because in my view MAV and ERB 
>are exactly as likely to "count a given vote" or not, that is, to 
>make a given gap in ratings between two candidates significant or 
>not). I'm not sure that explaining your Principle further would help 
>me understand it, because it's probably not going to fit with my 
>logic. I would, however, like to understand more about whether you 
>see the simplicity or the Principle as more important here.
>
>B. MAV vs. EMAV
>
>On this question, our principal disagreement is around the strategic 
>impact of the voting system, both for general exaggeration and for 
>specific chicken dilemma scenarios. Here's my logic:
>
>...Start Jameson's logic...
>
>1. In different systems, different strategies are effective. I'll 
>give one "5 candidate linear" (5CL) scenario and one chicken dilemma 
>(CD) scenario to illustrate my point.
>
>Honest utilities
>5CL:
>23: L100, CL75, CR25, R00, RR00
>25: L50, CL100, CR50, R00, RR00
>24: L00, CL50, CR100, R50, RR25
>22: L00, CL25, CR75, R100, RR50
>06: L00, CL00, CR25, R50, RR100
>
>(To make this comparison clearer, I'm going to use 4+1 ratings for 
>both systems, though it would actually work the same if under EMAV, 
>"25" represented a coinflip between the closest available ratings, 50 and 0)

EMAV uses 25% as a non-approved rating. Bucklin-ER could be voted 
with the coin flip, it does not have that below-expectation rating.

What I prefer to see is utilities that are normalized not only to the 
extremes, but also to the election expectation as midrange. This, in 
theory, could mean that the value of a point in the negative scale 
was different from that in the positive scale (i.e, below and above 
midrange.) Sophisticated voters would handle this by compressing the 
ratings at the extremes

It's quite true that this is not strictly summable. We could do a 
separate study to see how this translation affects utility. I'll 
note, however, that this is the test used in Approval Voting.

What I'm going to claim here, without having gone over the example, 
and presumably we will examine this, is that if the above are truly 
honest utilities -- we can treat them as absolute, not distorted by 
"strategy" -- and if 50 is the minimum acceptable rating, i.e,. the 
election expectation, the voter will not be disappointed by the 
election of a candidate rated 50, at least not by itself, then a 
reasonable voting strategy will be simple: vote the honest utilities 
as the ratings.

Now, as I start to go over this, I notice that all the voters have a 
candidate at each utility value. That's highly distorted from 
expectation. A voter, for example, who only knows their favorite may 
have a max *sincere* utility of 100, and zero for every other 
candidate. I don't know if this will impact the analysis. Ah, I see 
now that Jameson called this 5CL, "5 Candidate Linear." I read the 
votes this way:

23: L100, CL75, CR25, R00, RR00 voters at L
25: L50, CL100, CR50, R00, RR00 voters at CL, balanced between L and CR
24: L00, CL50, CR100, R50, RR25 voters at CR, balanced between CL and CR
22: L00, CL25, CR75, R100, RR50 voters at R
06: L00, CL00, CR25, R50, RR100 voters at RR

>CL is the honest winner under both MAV and EMAV, with a median of 50.

However, the utility numbers show a clearer picture:

SU for all the candidates from stated ratings taken as utilities, as 
percentage of maximum;
L : 35.50%
CL: 59.75%
CR: 60.25%
R : 37.00%
RR: 23.00%

CL is not the SU winner, it is CR, but only by 0.5%. An election this 
close would be unpredictable. It has, as well four candidates 
balanced by first preference, it's rare to have three. It's clearly 
been set up to do this.

How does this election proceed if the utilities are votes and with 
normal Bucklin amalgamation, majority is 50%+ :

         4       3       2
L       23      23      48
CL      25      48      72 majority
CR      24      46      71 majority
R       22      22      52 majority
RR      6       6       28

Three majorities!

Under EMAV, if there is a multiple majority at a round, the sum of 
ratings prevails, shown above, so CR would win with a very small 
margin, not CL as he stated.

Under ordinary Bucklin-ER, CL would win by a whisker. B-ER does not 
handle the lower ratings.

Under MAV, the election looks at the previous round, and CL wins 
there -- but also only by a small margin.

These methods are dithering with their introduced errors and a very 
small difference in utility.

>Under both systems, the CR voters could win by dropping CL's rating 
>to 25, and the CL voters could defend against this by dropping CR to 
>25. Under both, the RR voters could elect CR by rating them at 75 or 
>above. But EMAV presents a number of further possible strategies: 
>for instance, the R and L voters could both help their preferred 
>frontrunner by rating CR and CL at 100 and 0 or vice versa, whereas 
>with MAV these strategies would have no impact.

Indeed. What is utterly unrealistic here is the idea that the 
utilities would be voted as such. This is an election with *four 
first preference frontunners.* If a voter has a significant 
preference strength for their favorite, and 25% is significant, they 
will not immediately approve the second preference. They *may* 
approve this preference at a lower round, or even in the disapproved 
rank. Remember the basic strategy for Range, max rate the preferred 
frontrunner, min rate the worst, and then make the rest of the 
ratings as makes sense in relation to those? Some voters may do just 
this, others may back off from it a notch.

Let's see what this election looks like with more realistic votes. 
I'm going to assume that there is some history here, and that range 
poll data is available, because the plurality data will drive the 
voters nuts. The voters will know that the likely winners are CL and 
CR, and they will vote accordingly.

23: L100, CL75, CR00, R00, RR00 -- maintain preference for L, but min 
rate CR, the other frontrunner from CR
25: L50, CL100, CR00, R00, RR00 -- min rate CR
24: L00, CL00, CR100, R50, RR25 -- min rate CL
22: L00, CL00, CR75, R100, RR50 -- maintain preference for R, min rate CL
06: L00, CL00, CR75, R75, RR100 -- maintain preference for RR, uprate CR and R

Notice: I have the voters here maintain a first preference 
indication, which has a cost (1/4 vote in the frontrunner race). I'd 
like to see rating interpolation, remember? That would allow a 
half-rating to be used for that, reducing the cost to 1/8 vote.

The resulting strategic sums, percentage of max rating:

L       35.50
CL      42.25
CR      45.00
R       38.50
RR      23.00

Bucklin amalgamation:

L       23      23
CL      25      48
CR      24      52 majority
R       22      28
RR      6       6

CR wins again by B-ER, EMAV (which doesn't use the rating sum for 
this), and by MAV, because it's a single majority.

Notice that the sincere utility sums above were balanced for CL and 
CR, with a slight edge for CR. It was well above election expectation for both.

What sometimes happens in studying examples is that one faction is 
portrayed as using a strategy, while the other sits there stupid. But 
"strategy" here is simply sensible voting, and all factions are 
likely to use it to roughly the same extent. Notice that it doesn't 
make a big difference. The CR supporters simply accelerated their 
support, while keeping their first preference clear. They could have 
provided more support by going for 100% for CR, and the CL supporters 
could have done the same; both groups could pay the cost: failure to 
distinguish their favorite (i.e, L for CL and R or RR for CR).

52% of voters are at CR or to the right, 48% at CL or to the left. It 
is not a surprise that CR has an edge.

Various strategic patterns could flip this election between CR and 
CL, because strategy introduces error in utility representation, but 
the question is *how much* error?

This example, by the way, shows a superiority of EMAV over B-ER and MAV.

Jameson, I'm guessing, thinks that the possible strategic voting is 
an inherent negative. With five candidtaes, the five-rank system is a 
bit primitive. Vote interpolation would improve the resolution, 
allowing maintaining preference order while casting a more powerful 
vote. Voting systems theorists who think strategic voting is "bad" 
seem to want to prevent voters from using their power. That's 
favoring a theory over the empowerment of voters.

(Vote interpolation: the votes above were in five ranks, with a 
value, from first to last, of 4 to 0. Vote interpolation is a method 
of handling overvoting without discarding or seriously 
misrepresenting the intended vote, and it then has a use (just as 
counting all the votes has a use with plurality: it creates approval 
voting.) With vote interpolation, the highest and lowest rating 
marked for a candidate are averaged. So if one has a favorite and 
votes 4 (or 100 in the charts above), *and 3*, the vote is counted at 
a value of 3.5. Thus the cost of maintaining a designation of 
favorite is reduces to one-eighth of a vote, without the ballot 
becoming more complicated. It would actually be easy to use, one 
could mark straight ratings, then "nudge" them one way or the other.

This election is weird because if we look at first preference, we 
have *four* frontrunners. It's really that there are two major wings, 
and they each field two candidates, plus there is a small extreme 
right party with enough power to spoil an election if they choose -- 
or if the method doesn't allow them flexibility. This election is 
presented as partisan. In the setup, the right is split into *three* 
parties. That weakens them; the method barely saves their bacon. But 
notice, if they screw up, CL wins, and that is not actually a huge 
loss for them.

Jameson went on to cover a chicken dilemma scenario, but I'm bailing 
for the night, at least on this issue. I've queued it.




More information about the Election-Methods mailing list