[EM] article on preferential voting
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
abd at lomaxdesign.com
Sat Dec 30 07:42:26 PST 2006
At 09:11 AM 12/30/2006, jure.toplak at uni-mb.si wrote:
>I have prepared a paper on the definition of preferential voting. I
>invite all of you to check it. It is posted here:
>http://rcum.uni-mb.si/~jure/preferential8_emlist.pdf
Well, it is a bit irritating to me, and perhaps to some others, that
AV is used in the paper to refer to Alternative Vote; we routinely
use it for Approval Voting.
Approval is mentioned in the paper, however, in my view, incorrectly
(though perhaps merely reporting common opinion, in which case it is
correct about an incorrect opinion.)
Specifically,
>They apply the term to "those voting methods that make use of
>a preference schedule"10 including plurality first-past-the-post
>(FPTP) method, Concordet,
>and Borda count. The definition does not however cover approval voting.
Now, if "plurality" and FPTP use a "preference schedule," so does
Approval. The preference schedule in FPTP consists of two classes,
preferred and not-preferred, and the voter places the candidates into
the classes by either voting for the candidate or abstaining.
Generally, FPTP does not allow a voter to place more than one
candidate into the approved class, but this is actually a detail of
implementation having to do with ballot invalidation. That is, a
ballot-invalidation rule is tacked onto the voting system that
discards ballots who have approved more than the officially allowed
number of candidates, which is generally one with single-winner and N
with N-winner. This is an artificial restriction without, apparently,
much explicit justification.
If, for example, a show-of-hands election were being held in a
face-to-face meeting, there would generally be no bar to voters
raising their hand for more than one candidate, and I am sure that it
happens from time to time. It might even happen more than
occasionally, we would not normally know. Enough members at a meeting
may abstain to compensate for the "extra" votes which appear in the
reported counts. Only by specifically observing individual voters and
objecting if they vote more than once would we become aware of
"overvoting." It has never become an issue as far as I know, and the
basic reason is that there is utterly no harm in it.
Overvoting is essentially voting for every member of the approved
class over every non-member, with more than one member allowed in the
approved class. It is also equivalent to abstaining in the pairwise
vote between those approved members. Many systems with more than two
ranks allow voters to place more than one candidate at the same rank.
This is identical to Approval Voting, the only issue is how many
ranks are allowed. With Approval we assume there are two.
I've proposed a system called A+ where there are three ranks. The
Approved rank is split into two ranks: Approved and Preferred. One
may place more than one candidate into each of these ranks; however,
I assume that normally voters would only place one candidate into
Preferred, with any other approved candidates being placed into
Approved. In simple A+, the Preferred rank is considered merged with
the Approved rank, it is not used to determine the winner. However,
it may be used, for example, to determine ballot access rights and
public campaign funding, as well as to generate accurate poll
information, perhaps to monitor the performance of Approval vs the
possibility of moving to a system with more detailed ranks. It's a
small cost in ballot complexity for a substantial gain in gathered
information, and it answers the common objection to Approval that
voters want to express support for their favorite while still being
able to approve other candidates.
And then the same ballot is used for what I called A+/PW, for
Approval Plus/Pairwise, where, once again, Approvaed and Preferred
are considered identical in any pairwise race except for the pairwise
race(s) between Approved and Preferred candidates. This, of course,
is a Condorcet method with truncated ranks....
One clear advantage of Approval is that the ballot indicates Yes/No
for each candidate. The meaning, thus, of majority failure is clear,
the electorate has voted *against* all candidates, and, if sincere in
this, has essentially indicated that they would prefer to see the
office remain vacant than allow any of the candidates to be elected.
Under Roberts Rules, with the sequential motion method of electing
officers, which is the default, this is, indeed, exactly the decision
that voters are making when they vote for or against each motion to
elect So-and-So. (Of course, the problem with sequential motion is
that one may imagine that voters will vote against a candidate, not
because they are unwilling to accept the candidate, but because they
prefer another. However, I would ask why these voters did not move to
amend the motion to substitute their favorite for the one previously
named in it? Where such amendment is allowed, which I'd think it
would normally be, a motion to elect being like any other standard
motion -- at least it should be -- then election by specific motion
is fully Condorcet compatible. I think most of us have missed that.
The basic method of electing officers under Roberts Rules is
Condorcet-compatible. Substituting methods which are not for this,
based on the presumed inefficiency and impracticality of using
deliberative process for elections, would seem to be a loss. Now, are
there any methods which, as purely aggregative methods, simulate the
deliberative process?
Yes, there are.
Approval does it. It is a standard rule where multiple conflicting
motions are presented for simultaneous vote, that the motion with the
largest Yes vote prevails over passing motions with a lesser level of
approval. This is, precisely, Approval Voting. The common statement
that Approval is not used in public elections (with a couple of
exceptions sometimes being mentioned, such as the election of the
Secretary General of the United Nations) is not correct. It is used,
but not to elect officers, rather to simultaneously consider
conflicting referenda.
And that is what an election should be, a series of motions to elect
A, B, C, D, etc, with Yes/No votes possible. The only problem, and it
is a severe loss, is that the rules typically prevent voters from
voting for more than one. It is beyond me why. The assumption seems
to be, where a reason is given or implied at all, that such votes are
clearly mistakes, voter error, and thus, as errors, should be disregarded.
But, quite often, they are not errors, except in the sense that the
voter did not realize that the arbitrary no-overvote rule would
apply. A naive voter -- and many would be naive in this way -- may
think that the votes will simply be counted. Why not?
I have been asking for some time for cogent reasons that overvotes
should cause ballots to be discarded. What I've gotten so far, as I
recall, is this:
(1) If overvotes are allowed, fraud become easier. I could take a
vote for A and add a vote for B by simply making the additional mark.
I find this argument puzzling. For I can invalidate, with the
no-overvote rule, ballots by doing just this, thus committing fraud.
The no-overvote rule does not prevent fraud, and, indeed, it could be
shown that it makes fraud simpler; together with other rules that are
essentially aimed at preventing voters from revealing their identity,
it makes it very easy to damage and cause ballots to be discarded.
Generally, just make a mark on the ballot. In order to prevent voters
from identifying their vote, perhaps to interdict those who would
coerce or buy votes from verifying compliance, we risk -- and
probably actually enable -- other kinds of election fraud. Vote
buying does happen, but it is quite hazardous, even charges of
vote-buying, coupled with sufficient evidence that something that may
have made vote-buying possible, without proof that it actually took
place, have resulted in the overturn of an election and the
declaration of the former loser as the winner. Buying votes can ruin
your election, even if you would have won without doing it, and
buying enough votes to really make a difference is difficult.
(Suarez vs. Carollo, Miami mayor race, I think it was about 1997.
Some supporters of Suarez transported voters to a
registration/absentee voting location and offered to pay them small
sums. With this was made a suggested vote, but there was no
allegation of coercion, nor, indeed that they were actually being
paid to vote a certain way, nor even that the votes were monitored.
There was however, evidence that some of these registrations were
fraudulent, which was not necessarily the fault of the Suarez
supporters. Because the total of absentee ballots resulted in Carollo
not gaining a majority, thus automatically causing a runoff election
to be held -- which Suarez won -- the court ultimately decided to
discard *all* absentee ballots. Given that Suarez -- who was not
implicated in the alleged vote-buying -- won the runoff even if
absentee ballots were discarded, it is pretty likely that Suarez
legitimately won the election if only fraudulent ballots could have
been identified and discarded. But because there was no way to
discriminate between fraudulent and non-fraudulent ballots, and the
court ruled that absentee voting was a privilege and not a right, it
decided to discard *all* absentee votes, thus systematically
disenfranchising the population that must vote in that way. Which is
quite likely not to be identical in preference to the direct voting
population. Generally, vote-buying is illegal, and to have much
effect, it must be a crime that is very difficult to conceal.)
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list