[EM] Re: [instantrunoff] Drafft of CVD analysis about IRV vs. Condorcet Voting
Dave Ketchum
davek at clarityconnect.com
Fri Apr 2 20:23:02 PST 2004
On Fri, 2 Apr 2004 10:11:03 EST democracyusa at aol.com wrote on instantrunoff:
> Greetings,
>
> As advocates of instant runoff voting, we have tried to focus on the
> case for instant runoff voting over the plurality and delayed runoff
> systems already used in the United States. But as many of you may know,
> some of our most vigorous opponents are supporters of other single
> winner reform approaches. We wish they would focus their energy on
> seeking support for their system compared to plurality and runoffs, as
> we do. Some indeed do that, but it hasn't been the case for others.
>
> There are good reasons for why we support instant runoff voting over
> alternatives. The analysis below is in draft form, and Terry Bouricus
> (tbouricius at verizon.net) is our point-person in finalizing it. If you
> have any comments or suggestions, please let him know. Note that when we
> post it on the web, we will have a short summary for those who don't
> want to get into as much detail.
>
Others have noticed this post, and written about it on election-methods.
There Condorcet AND IRV are recognized as better than competitors such as
Plurality. I will try for more detail, as a Condorcet backer.
> - Rob Richie
>
> ########
> Instant Runoff Voting vs. Condorcet Voting
>
> Among proposals to reform the way we elect single-winner offices,
> instant runoff voting (IRV) is by far the most popular and has gained
> significant traction in states and cities around the nation. But there
> is persistent criticism of IRV by some advocates of other alternative
> voting methods. This analysis compares IRV with Condorcet voting, a
> ranked-choice system favored by some mathematicians. We conclude that
> IRV is better than Condorcet voting both for theoretical and pragmatic
> reasons.
>
Certainly IRV has LOUD VOCAL backing.
Note that Condorcet and IRV use identical ballots and usually agree as to
winner - only cases where they disagree provide ammunition for debate.
> As a first overall point, Kenneth Arrow won the Nobel Prize in part for
> proving that every single-seat election system inevitably violates some
> reasonable measure of "fairness," in at least some circumstances. It
> therefore is possible to find a flaw in every method of voting. That is,
> there is no such thing as a perfect voting system -- one must assess how
> harmful and how frequent the "pathological" outcomes will be under each
> system, and how each system will enhance or worsen campaigns and
> political discourse.
>
> A second general point is that there are two fundamental classes of
> voting systems that fulfill different purposes. IRV, Condorcet voting
> and all systems for electing offices in which only one person wins (such
> as a mayor, governor, president or a legislator representing a
> single-member district) are "winner-take-all" systems. No
> winner-take-all system is ideal for electing a legislative body, such as
> a city council, or state or national legislature. In those cases, some
> form of full representation (also called proportional representation) is
> more representative. Full representation voting systems assure that the
> majority of voters will elect the majority of the legislative seats, but
> also, that significant minorities will be able to elect their fair share
> of seats (in proportion to their support among the electorate). The
> discussion below is limited to a comparison of two single-seat
> majoritarian winner-take-all systems - IRV and Condorcet.
>
> Turning to single winner elections, then, we believe that there are
> several voting methods that would better serve the public interest than
> traditional plurality methods. We focus our reform energies on IRV
> because we believe it is the best of these systems and one with strong
> political potential in the United States. See our extensive webpages
> describing IRV. [LINK ON SITE TO www.fairvote.org/irv]
>
> Like IRV, Condorcet voting is an "ordinal" system in which voters rank
> candidates. Candidates are compared on every person's ballot, and the
> candidate who theoretically could defeat all other candidates in
> one-on-one races based on these pair-wise comparisons is declared the
> winner. If there is no such candidate, (such as Candidate A beats
> Candidate B, Candidate B beats Candidate C, but C beats A) some fallback
> system, such as IRV, must be used to select a winner.
>
Condorcet backers recognize this problem and debate as to solutions.
Usual method is to disqualify the "weakest" of the conflicting pairs,
rather than involving some other method such as IRV.
> Both IRV and Condorcet provide these improvements:
>
> 1. They prevent the election of a candidate whom the majority thinks is
> the worst choice (a quite plausible occurrence under plurality voting in
> a three-way race).
Time to throw rocks. Assume 40 like A; 60 like B, seeing A as worst
choice; and 31 of the 60 are enchanted with C as EVEN BETTER than B. Laid
out more formally (note that, as I would expect, these voters ONLY vote
their serious positive interests):
40 A
31 C>B
29 B
Condorcet will see 60B>40A, 40A>31C. and 31C>29B. I expect the C>B to be
discarded as weakest, declaring B as winner.
IRV must discard the 29 B as weakest, after which the unwanted A becomes
the obvious winner.
> 2. They accommodate more parties and candidates, by eliminating the
> "spoiler" issue for parties that cannot yet gain enough votes to win.
> Having more choices from across the spectrum deepens political
> discussion and allows new parties to disseminate their message and grow
> (or not) organically over a period of years.
>
Mostly agreed - note that C becomes a "spoiler" for IRV above.
Also note that multiple candidates competing for the same voters is not
the disaster that it can be in Plurality.
> Condorcet advocates suggest that it has advantages over IRV. For
> example, in some rare cases a voter in an IRV election can hurt a
> candidate by ranking that candidate more highly. Although technically
> true, its importance is negligible because such a rare mathematical
> possibility is almost impossible to anticipate before an election and
> thus of no tactical significance. One would have to know that one of
> your more favored candidates would be been benefited by the elimination
> of one of your more disapproved candidates before a later runoff round
> of counting. In decades of important IRV elections in Australia and
> Ireland, this alleged flaw in IRV has caused no problems or
> controversies - and is no different from the Monday morning
> quarterbacking one can do under any election system.
>
> IRV critics who prefer Condorcet also point out that in some scenarios,
> voters in an IRV system could improve the chances of their second
> favorite candidate defeating their least favorite candidate by
> strategically ranking their second choice as number one instead of their
> true favorite candidate (assuring the strongest acceptable candidate
> makes it into the final runoff count, for example, ahead of a candidate
> whom many people like better, but does not have enough centrist appeal
> to win in a runoff). Because of this example they argue incorrectly that
> Condorcet voting is the only system that escapes 100% from insincere
> strategic voting and from the spoiler problem.
>
> In fact Condorcet also creates incentives for insincere voting. All the
> mathematical elegance of Condorcet Voting is irrelevant when it can be
> so obviously gamed through insincere strategic voting. Strategic voting
> occurs when voters have an incentive to rank candidates in an order
> contrary to their true preferences in order to help a preferred
> candidate or block another candidate. Although strategic voting may be
> possible with any voting system, it is in fact a larger problem with
> Condorcet than with IRV.
>
Huh!
> Suppose four candidates (A, B, C, and D) are running for an office,
> where candidates A and B are the frontrunners. Consider a voter whose
> true preferences are in order of A, B, C, D. Under Condorcet, by voting
> insincerely this voter can minimize the chances that candidate B will
> defeat his or her preferred candidate A. A voter quickly realizes that
> the best strategy is to punish the strongest competitor to her favorite
> candidate by ranking the candidates insincerely A, C, D, B. Doing so may
> block B - and any candidate -- from becoming the Condorcet winner and
> improve candidate A's chances to win under the fallback rule. Worse yet,
> if both A and B supporters widely engage in such strategic voting, the
> winner could be a candidate most voters actually oppose, but didn't
> realize would benefit from their insincere rankings. With IRV, there
> rarely is an incentive to engage in strategic voting, since later
> rankings do not hurt earlier rankings. In certain unique situations
> where there is widespread availability of detailed polling information,
> there are ways to vote strategically with IRV, but strategic voting is
> greatly limited. There is no rule of general applicability of the value
> of insincere rankings, as there is with Condorcet.
>
Huh! By ranking A first the voter has said as much as possible as to A vs
B. Ranking A,C,D,B in Condorcet ONLY indicates liking C and D better than
B - doing that if you do not dislike B that much is a stupid
misunderstanding of strategy.
> Condorcet has even more important negatives directly related to its
> seemingly sensible goal of selecting the candidate who theoretically
> would beat all others in a one-on-one race. Its biggest flaw is that it
> can elect a candidate who has too little support to be seen as a good
> representative of substantial numbers of voters - a candidate so lacking
> in support to ever be competitive in a traditional plurality or runoff
> election. At an extreme, the Condorcet winner in a four-candidate race
> might be unable to win a single vote in our current election system, but
> could win under Condorcet by avoiding being any voters' last choice. In
> other words, the Condorcet winner's ability to defeat all other
> candidates in a one-on-one race is entirely theoretical because in an
> election held under plurality or runoff rules, their lack of core
> support would prevent then from ever being opposed by just one candidate.
>
This is a debate topic. I like modifying my above case a bit via 29 D>B -
all of the basically B voters like either C or D better - but those who
like C see D as an enemy and D voters return the compliment. In your
words, B has no core support - BUT - MAJORITIES like A or C or D LESS!
BTW - B might do better in Plurality than in IRV - unable to vote for B
PLUS C or D, at least some likely would vote for B.
> Here is an election scenario that demonstrates this problematic dynamic
> in Condorcet voting.
>
> Imagine a polarized election in which:
> Candidate A is favored by 55% of voters who all disapprove of candidate B,
> Candidate B is favored by 45% of voters who all disapprove of candidate A.
>
> Now suppose candidate C joins the race and stresses his/her likeability
> and avoids any controversial issues.
>
> If 15% of the A supporters are drawn to candidate C's friendly image,
> the result would now be:
>
> Candidate A=40%
> Candidate B=45%
> Candidate C=15%.
>
> Under plurality rules, Candidate B wins even though 55% of all voters
> consider Candidate B the worst choice
>
NOT fatal - voters are doing the best they can in Plurality - their
attraction to C has impacted their liking for A..
> Both IRV and Condorcet always avoid this fatal flaw. Under IRV rules,
> Candidate C is eliminated in the runoff count and Candidate A again wins
> with 55%.
>
I accept your desire - BUT - it does not count unless you say it more
clearly.
> Under Condorcet rules, however, if Candidate A's supporters rank
> Candidate C above Candidate B whom they detest, and B supporters also
> rank C second because of disdain for A, candidate C can win. Because the
> Condorcet winner may be someone who nobody considers a particularly good
> candidate, it punishes candidates who take clear stands on controversial
> issues and rewards candidates who say little of substance.
>
More clearly, please. If you say the voters LIKE C, even IRV might agree
as to winner.
> Theoreticians must understand that the measuring tool (the voting
> system) can change candidate behavior and the information voters have
> for assessing them. The logic of Condorcet promotes a campaign strategy
> that is detrimental to political discourse and voters' ability to get
> the information needed to assess candidates. It primarily encourages
> avoiding alienating voters, and discourages taking stands on potentially
> divisive issues. Over a series of Condorcet elections we believe most
> major candidates would avoid taking clear policy stands, and in turn
> thus likely lead to lower voter turnout and less well-informed voters.
>
Huh! As I said earlier, IRV and Condorcet USUALLY will agree as to
winner, meaning that, except for IRV strategy attempts, the same arguments
apply to both.
> IRV provides a better balance between the competing values of being
> representative of substantial numbers of voters and of having broad
> appeal. IRV encourages candidates to distinguish themselves and to have
> sufficient boldness to win many first-choice rankings, but it also
> encourages candidates to reach out to supporters of other candidates and
> avoid vilifying them in overly negative attacks. This is a desirable
> incentive package.
>
Ditto.
> A voting system does not just select winners. A voting system shapes the
> nature of political debate, and largely dictates how well informed most
> voters are able to be. An inoffensive candidate who studiously avoids
> taking any controversial stands, but simply campaigns by projecting an
> image of being friendly and honest can be everybody's acceptable
> compromise and win with Condorcet even if nobody considered him/her the
> best candidate. While plurality voting over-values the ability to be a
> voter's first choice, Condorcet overvalues the value of ability to avoid
> being voters' last choice. IRV provides a compromise by giving
> appropriate weight to both values.
>
Ditto.
> We also believe reformers must weigh pragmatic considerations. We
> welcome Condorcet voting advocates seeking to persuade voters and
> elected officials to support their preferred system over plurality
> elections and runoff elections, just as IRV advocates do. But we believe
> that efforts to adopt IRV are far more likely to be successful. The fact
> that Condorcet all too possibly could elect a candidate who would come
> in dead last in a traditional American plurality or runoff election
> essentially makes it a political non-starter - both from the perspective
> of ordinary voters and of elected officials. In contrast, IRV has a
> widely-accepted analog: the traditional runoff election that Americans
> use in many elections and that most nations use around the world when
> electing a president. The fact that many people are familiar with
> runoffs and appreciate their logic helps IRV advocates fend off attacks
> by opponents. Indeed recent wins at the polls, growing support from
> civic leaders and editorial writers and activity in half of our state
> legislatures indicate IRV's viability.
>
Sales pitch. Agreed that IRV backers talk louder, and have made some
sales. Condorcet, more like a tournament, needs better selling.
Do think that, assuming IRV complete vote counts get published, as
Condorcet backers can easily do, IRV will get its own embarrassment.
BTW - IRV CLAIMS a majority votes for its declared winner. Given about
1/3 of voters bullet voting for each of 3 candidates, there IS NO majority.
--
davek at clarityconnect.com people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek
Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026
Do to no one what you would not want done to you.
If you want peace, work for justice.
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list