[EM] Droop fails the Markus Schulze Rule
Craig Carey
research at ijs.co.nz
Tue Oct 19 07:03:53 PDT 1999
At 22:57 19.10.99 , Markus Schulze wrote:
>Dear Craig,
>
>you wrote (19 Oct 1999):
>> At 21:16 18.10.99 , Markus Schulze wrote:
>> > I want to add that (in so far as most election methods don't
>> > guarantee that a voter cannot be punished for going to the polls
>> > and voting sincerely) the concept of wasted votes cannot really
>> > be used as a criterion. It is only a heuristic like Blake
>> > Cretney's aim to find the "best guess for the best candidate."
>> > The reason: The concept of wasted votes implicitly presumes that
>> > every voter wants to be counted; but a voter who worsens the
>> > election result (by going to the polls and voting sincerely)
>> > rather wants to be ignored than counted. This is also the reason
>> > why Michael Dummett rejects the concept of wasted votes.
>>
>> When a voter casts a vote, that vote shifts the point
>> representing the election outcome by some amount towards the
>> point representing the voter's vote. Given that the point of
>> the election outcome exists if the voter does vote, then if the
>> voter doesn't turn up and vote, the voter is effectively casting
>> a negative vote and the election's point goes back to where it
>> was. So not voting is little different from voting, in that the
>> point representing the election outcome is moved by some distance.
>>
>> Mr Schulze may be wrong when saying voters want to be ignored:
>> That seems to presume that the voter has not got a full knowledge
>> of the method and the paper counts. Some of the persons advocating
>> their positions had a knowledge of an instance where number made
>> their stance correct.
>
>Do you question that some election methods sometimes punish voters
>for going to the polls and voting sincerely? Or do you question that
>a voter rather wants to have no influence on the election result than
>to worsen the election result?
>
>Markus Schulze
---------
There are two questions. To the first I reply: no, election methods
can punish voters for voting. A proof could involve an analysis of
voting method devised to allow the proof to proceed easily, e.g.
a method too defective to be used in practice.
To the second question, I'd reply:
The topic is about individual humans (unless programs in some
electoral methods contest with strategic voting done by programs),
and what they want. They have not got a perfect knowledge of the
paper counts or ratios, during a actual vote. Either they'll
risk doing the wrong thing, or there is no risk, or an analysis
of the election has been made. What happens in practice is that
voters cast votes in a way they themselves could say not optimal
if later given all the facts. But the more that get the facts
after the election, the less accurate the election outcome data
would be.
I am one of those that write to this list that take the opinion
that the intent and wishes and hopes and concerns of voters,
and their individual and collective will, their futures, their
disliking for rain, and ultimately, their humanity in crises like
the Labrador dog being profoundly sick, should be absolutely
and totally ignored. Is that how it is in your region of the
world Mr Schulze?.
I have yet to find a method or formula that actually contains a
'term' representing voters wishes. The Borda method doesn't have
such a term, and some of these STV experts could give an opinion
about that method.
You wrote "do you question that a voter rather wants...".
Why use the word "wants" ?.
How is that idea used twice so that it becomes more than an idle
and fruitless definition?.
The estimation of the quantity of wants not only creates a basis
asking for involvement of statisticians, but psychologists too.
Mr Schulze most definitely did use the word wants, and maybe it
had a special meaning that did not include the usual English
meaning of the word "want".
It is simple to replace it: For example, if the set of winners in
an election are {B, E, G}, and if a preferential voting paper
under consideration is (A B C D E F), then the election outcome
satisfies the paper by this amount given by this number:
(A wins)+(B wins)/2+(C wins)/4+(D wins)/8+(E wins)/16+(F wins)/32
= 0 + 1/2 + 0/4 + 0/8 + 1/16 + 0/32
= 9/16.
For a single paper only, different outcomes (sets of winners)
could be compared.
(Replacing a "voter" with the competing concept: "voting paper",
has a problem quite fixable in the construction of rules, which
is that more than one voter may have contributed to a single
paper's count.)
To reply (by commenting) to two messages at once, I note that
Mr Catchpole had written:
>
>Let Pi(A,B:V) represent the truth of whether voter i prefers candidate A
>over B in voting schema V.
>
>Let W(V) represent the set of winners of voting schema V
>
>For all V, all V', W(V)<>W(V') implies-
>
>there exists i, A, B such that A is an element of W(V), A is not an
>element of W(V'), B is an element of W(V'), B is not an element of W(V),
>not Pi(B,A,V),not Pi(A,B,V')
Quite apart from which of those commas are logical conjunctions and
which are implication operators, and the seeming excessive weakness
of the statement, and the pairwise formulation which is best avoided
since it makes a rule less useful in mathematics, I note the words:
"...the truth of whether voter i prefers...".
Could "truth" mean an approximation made by Condorcet pairwise comparing?,
rather than what people tend to understand by that word. A precise
definition of the use of something that is never known or properly
defined. That would be OK if the aim was to prevent all progress
and obscure the cause for that.
>> let p:A be the list truncated at the preference for candidate A.
>> B beats A in a Condorcet sense if (B in p:A), and 'in' treats the
>> RHS list as if a set. Whether it is better to have (A in p:A)
>> or not is not obvious.
>
>This itself is unclear. What do you mean? Does (B in p:A) represent the
>number of voters who favour B over A? Clearly there's a cultural
>difference here which can only be resolved through beginning again from
>first principles and _not_ attempting to express principles solely through
>a quasi set algebra.
Since Mr Catchpole recently sought to minimise the truth that
"set" theory had a place in preferential voting theory.
Ms Nadine Strossen, president of the US ACLU (American Civil Liberties
Union) was criticised by Senator Alston in August 1999 for stating that
Australia was the (or, a) "global village idiot". (I wrote to the
EFA (Electronic Frontiers Australia) "Stop-Censorship mailing list
asking for a more believable defence, than the "cultural differences"
defence made out by the Senator. No one replied.
Set theory in prefeential voting theory:
-----------------------------------------------------------------------
Loading image file :R:\REDUCE\ZIB\fix95\bin\win95\reduce.img
REDUCE 3.6, 15-Jul-95 ...
1: forall w,p let want(w,p)=for k:=1:length(p) sum if member(part(p,k),w) then 2**(-k) else 0;
Declare want operator ? (Y or N)
?y
2: want({b,e,g},{a,b,c,d,e,f});
9
----
32
-----------------------------------------------------------------------
"member(A,S)" = (A in S); "part(p,k)" = p[k].
When people talk about wishes of voters but not numbers like 9/32
or anythig at all that has to do with ballots, how is that
compatible with an idea like : 'the counts of the papers decide
the winners' ?.
Errata:
I had written this:
:If the rule applies to a single paper, then the weight of the
: paper is the distance of the point representing the election
: to the face opposing the paper's vertex. The rule defines a
: region around the election point that extends outwards by that
: distance. (Q1) says that that region shall not intersect a
: win-lose boundary.
That is wrong in that one papers for voters can shift the election
outcome by the distance allowed by the paper's voting weight, but
the (Q1) violation does not occur at all win-lose surfaces
intersecting the region around the outcome's point, but only
at those win-lose surfaces where the outcome on the far side
would give a larger (binary) paper-satisfaction (Q1) number.
I note that some countries have privacy laws, and the wishes of
voters can't be obtained all that easily. There seems to be
more than enough information about how politicians complain
about faults in STV of AV. That information does not vary from
election to election.
I disagree with Mr Donaldson & Mr Round and some others, who
have been aiming to make arguments by using some process of
'understanding'. A problem with that particular method of
reasoning (or thinking), in the case of issues about STV's
properties, is that STV is complex and a rigourous or adequate
treatment of how that complexity does not invalidate the
plausible (or not plausible) understanding-based argument,
hasn't been occurring. Probably there should be a particular
reference to all paragraphs in documents that define STV.
__________________________________________________________________
Mr G. A. Craig Carey E-mail: research at ijs.co.nz
Auckland, Nth Island, New Zealand
Pages: Snooz Metasearch: http://www.ijs.co.nz/info/snooz.htm
MEDLINE (PubMed), Public Proxies, Multithreaded Add-URL DNSLookup
__________________________________________________________________
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list