[EM] Droop fails the Markus Schulze Rule
Craig Carey
research at ijs.co.nz
Mon Oct 18 15:50:11 PDT 1999
It seems to me that numbers created by computers ought
decide the significance of the difference between Droop
and Hare. Coding up such a program would immediately run
into the problem that a "wasted vote" is not defined.
In this message I give a definition of vote wastage after
taking note of the idea that STV has transfer values that
are not always equal to 1.
At 21:16 18.10.99 , Markus Schulze wrote:
>Dear participants,
>
>I don't agree with Donald that the task of an election method
>is to allocate voters to candidates. To my opinion, the task
>of an election method is to allocate to a given combination of
>opinions of the voters a set of n winners (where n is the number
>of seats).
>
>Thus the number of wasted votes cannot be defined as the number
>of voters who cannot be allocated to a winning candidate.
>The number of wasted votes must rather be defined as the number
>of voters in the largest set A with the following property:
>Independently on how the voters of this set A vote, the election
>result will always be the same.
>
That might not be satisfactory.
Mr Schulze's definition is not about methods, but about
methods and particular ratio of voting paper counts.
The definition seems to be the shortest distance between
a point that represents the ballots/counts, and the nearest
boundary to some 2 candidates' win-lose regions, inside the
simplex.
'Distance' doesn't mean Euclidean distance. For example, suppose
only 4 types of papers are allowed. Then to alter the election
paper ratios so that the point representing the election, moves
from one vertex to another (e.g. from (1,0,0,0) to (0,1,0,0)),
a 100% change of papers will be required.
Moving the point representing the election from a vertex to the
centre of that vertices's opposing face is a shorter Euclidean
distance but it still a 100% change of the votes
(for example: from (1,0,0,0) to (0,1/3,1/3,1/3)).
Suppose Mr Davison considered all this and then coloured the
regions containing points where the FPTP boundary was a closer
boundary than the boundary of the method under consideration
(STV). It doesn't matter where the 2 faces are: they will have
points on both sides. Replacing FPTP with a competing STV
doesn't alter the fact that large volumes contain points that
favour the nearer win-lose surface, even when the two interior
surfaces are permitted to almost merge.
The idea of Mr Shulze needs to take account of hypervolumes,
but it seems to be understood too well.
>[I want to add that (in so far as most election methods don't
>guarantee that a voter cannot be punished for going to the polls
>and voting sincerely) the concept of wasted votes cannot really
>be used as a criterion. It is only a heuristic like Blake
>Cretney's aim to find the "best guess for the best candidate."
>The reason: The concept of wasted votes implicitly presumes that
>every voter wants to be counted; but a voter who worsens the
>election result (by going to the polls and voting sincerely)
>rather wants to be ignored than counted. This is also the reason
>why Michael Dummett rejects the concept of wasted votes.]
>
>Markus Schulze
When a voter casts a vote, that vote shifts the point
representing the election outcome by some amount towards the
point representing the voter's vote. Given that the point of
the election outcome exists if the voter does vote, then if the
voter doesn't turn up and vote, the voter is effectively casting
a negative vote and the election's point goes back to where it
was. So not voting is little different from voting, in that the
point representing the election outcome is moved by some distance.
Mr Schulze may be wrong when saying voters want to be ignored:
That seems to presume that the voter has not got a full knowledge
of the method and the paper counts. Some of the persons advocating
their positions had a knowledge of an instance where number made
their stance correct.
In any case, if a voter wants candidate A firstly then B second, and
the voting method would make A lose and C win if A was voted
for, then instead of not voting, the voter might wish to vote for
candidate D just to cause the method to make B win, if that was
a way to get the desired result.
This is all part of the rule, (Q1), below.
--------------
It should be possible to define wasted votes and find out if
Mr Donald Davison is wrong or in the right, and by how much,
in the Hare-STV vs. Droop-STV discussion.
Note that since FPTP is a one of the worst methods at wasting
votes, and since it satisfies monotonicity and (P1), then
wasting of votes has nothing much to do with those two
definitions or rules.
STV wastes votes because of its use of "transfer values".
That is well known about STV. The complex CPO-STV method is a
variant of STV that is said by its designer(s) to be designed
to minimise loss of the effect of votes.
That "transfer value" idea can be generalised so it applies to
all methods. That is done below.
--------------
Examples of what seems to be wasting of the power of votes.
[1] There would be a "wasted vote" if a change led to this:
(1)
10 (A B C D E F) : {B} = {A,B,C,D,E,F}.(set of Winners)
(2)
7 (A B)
3 (A F) : {B,F} = {A,B,C,D,E,F}.(set of Winners)
System (2) shows that 30% of the vote can elect candidate F.
In system (1), that 30% got lost when being "transferred" over
preferences (B C D E).
[2] There would be a wasted vote if a change led to this:
(1)
10 (A B C D E F) : {C,D,E,F} = {A,B,C,D,E,F}.Winners
(2)
3 (C D E F)
7 (B) : {B} = {A,B,C,D,E,F}.Winners
It seems to be too strong to require that methods not have any
instance of votes being wasted due to preceding losing
preferences. For example, votes get wasted over the preference
for B, in the (B C) paper, in this election:
(1)
5 A .
4 B C <-- Votes are not transferred to C
2 C A : STV, IFPP, FPTP: {A} = Winner
(2)
5 A .
4 C
2 C A : STV, IFPP, FPTP: {C} = Winner
A definition of a rule:
--------------------------------------------------------------
RULE (Q1) 19-Oct-1999
Regard a voting paper as a binary number, with each preference
replaced by 1 if the candidate won and by 0 if the candidate
lost. Then this rule is not satisfied if the voter could
increase the value of the binary number by altering the paper
in any way (including dividing it). Alterations are however
constrained by a requirement that the weight of the paper be
not altered by any factor less than 0 or greater than 1.
--------------------------------------------------------------
Violations of (Q1) can be integrated. The (Q1) rule is too
strong to be used to reject preferential voting methods
for any instance of noncompliance.
If the rule applies to a single paper, then the weight of the
paper is the distance of the point representing the election
to the face opposing the paper's vertex. The rule defines a
region around the election point that extends outwards by that
distance. (Q1) says that that region shall not intersect a
win-lose boundary.
The relative hypervolume for a particular method could be
calculated. A computer could do that. The value found could
be compared against the value found for FPTP. Perhaps all
methods with a (Q1) failure figure that exceeds FPTP's for
any number of winners and candidates, could be ruled out.
Having an aim of minimising the wastage of votes, measured
by points where (Q1) is not satisfied, isn't able to coexist
particularly well with another aim, say proportionality.
Possibly "proportionality" can be defined to be (Q1).
In my last message I gave a seemingly different way to find
a proportional method. I am fair from clear that the two
formulations would give the same result.
Has anybody got the ideas 'vote wastage' and 'proportionality'
defined well enough, to be able to explain the essentials
of the difference(s) between the two?.
G. A. Craig Carey, Avondale, Auckland, 19 Oct 1999
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list