[EM] Sincere voting
Joe Weinstein
jweins123 at hotmail.com
Thu Dec 14 18:23:39 PST 2000
Many recent EM-list postings unwittingly illustrate how hard it is to define
- let alone fruitfully exploit - the notion of a given vote (voter's ballot
marking) being sincere'. Sincerity' per se seems a fruitless quest, but
our interest in the concept does reflect our key concern - election methods
which allow voters' desires to be more readily expressed and realized. The
following comments examine just how and why sincerity' is so problematic -
in general and in voting.
Joe Weinstein
Long Beach CA USA
SINCERITY' IN GENERAL. Here's a working general definition. A person's
utterance - or a similar expressive action, e.g. a vote (marking of a
ballot) - is sincere' (and the person is sincere', at least in making the
utterance or in casting the vote) if the beliefs or attitudes conveyed by
the utterance are in accord with the person's body of relevant beliefs (or
attitudes).
Various disagreements found in recent EM-list postings owe to the
significant INHERENT ambiguities in the above (or similar) notion of
sincerity. These arise at least from the following ambiguities in the above
key terms conveyed', accord', and relevant'.
Conveyed'. Beliefs (or attitudes) are covert and private, whereas
utterances are overt and public. In effect, a belief is an expression
within a rich covert language, which may or may not readily translate
exactly - or even to what may be deemed good-enough approximation - into the
overt language used in an utterance. Just which relevant beliefs are thus
conveyed' by the utterance? Presence of sincerity' must depend on the
answer taken to this question.
Accord'. As the term accord' indicates, sincerity requires that a
certain logical relationship exist between the relevant beliefs conveyed by
the utterance and the totality of the utterer's relevant beliefs. Exactly
what is this relationship? A MINIMAL concept of accord' requires only that
the utterance NOT CONTRADICT utterer's relevant beliefs. A MAXIMAL concept
requires that the utterance AFFIRM ALL these beliefs (i.e., not only be a
truth' but the whole truth', which usually is a practical impossibility).
Intermediate (usually vaguer) requirements are that the utterance must
affirm a sufficiently salient part of these beliefs.
Relevant'. Presence of sincerity' typically depends not on all beliefs
but just on relevant' ones. Relevance may depend highly on the context.
For instance, when your hearer is anxiously awaiting your declaration of
love (or possibly of rejection), you may be judged highly insincere if you
exclaim 2+2=4', even though you do truly and even intensely believe that
2+2=4.
Each of these three terms is actually triply ambiguous, because it leaves
open just who - ourselves, the utterer, or the listener - is to be the judge
that resolves the term's ambiguity.
VOTING EXAMPLE. Suppose that your attitudes include evaluations for four
candidates, A-D, using ratings (on a scale of 0.00 to 1.00): A=0.75,
B=0.75, C=0.45, D= 0.00. Now suppose that you vote: you mark the ballot by
giving each candidate an integer grade (zero or higher).
The prevalent lone-mark (i.e. plurality') method allows just one nonzero
grade, namely a 1 (pass'). Suppose your lone pass is for A. Does your
vote qualify as sincere' or not? In one sense, it is as sincere as the
method allows it to be; in another sense, it is quite insincere (albeit such
insincerity is forced by the method) as it does not at all come close to
expressing what you or maybe others deem important aspects of my evaluation:
that A and B are rated equally, and that B and C are each far closer to A
than to D.
Now suppose you revote under the pass-fail (i.e. approval') method, which
allows any set of pass (=1) and fail(=0) grades. Suppose your vote is: A=1,
B=1, C=1, D=0. Is this vote sincere'? In one sense, it is as sincere as
the method allows it to be. Namely, candidates evaluated above some
threshold (e.g. 0.40) get passed, while the others get failed. Moreover,
this particular vote gives as large as possible gap between the lowest-rated
passed candidate and the highest-rated failed candidate. However, in
another sense the vote is quite insincere (and this time not because the
method forces it to be), as it gives to B the grade 1 rather than 0,
although B's rating is closer to 0 than to 1. Another insincerity (which
also holds with lone-mark) is forced by the fact that only two grades are
available, so that your vote cannot express the fact that your degrees of
preference for A over C and for C over D are both significant.
Now revote under a strict-only ranking method, e.g. iterated reduction
(instant runoff') or usual Borda. Suppose your vote is: A=3, B=2, C=1,
D=0. (A is top choice, etc.) Much the same arguments for sincerity and
insincerity apply as were cited above for lone-mark (plurality').
The above-cited contradictory informal judgments of sincerity and
insincerity all reflect various opinionated but plausible choices which
could be made by a minimalist (on the issue of accord) to resolve the
above-noted ambiguities of conveyance. (Meanwhile, for a maximalist,
typically no vote at all can qualify as sincere.) For some minimalists in
some cases, vote truncation (so that, for example, only candidate A receives
a grade) might change their view of the vote from insincere to sincere, as
the vote would contain fewer specifications which might be deemed to
contradict significant features of the set of ratings.
Among other things, we see that - under usual resolutions of ambiguities of
conveyance and accord - each of the above-discussed methods often (i.e., for
many sets of ratings, as in the above example) permits no sincere vote
whatever.
The underlying reason is quite simple: none of the methods always allows
grades which simply and directly express your ratings, but rather each
method imposes constraints on the allowed grades. (For the case of
pass-fail, the constraint arises from the low resolution of the grading,
i.e. just two grades are available. Each other method has, instead or in
addition, a trade-off constraint: a higher grade for one candidate requires
a lower grade for some other candidate.)
In order to avoid being embarrassed when no sincere vote is possible for you
under my favorite method, I might try to exploit the third ambiguity source:
relevance. Now, few people overtly deny the relevance of ratings of
candidates, at least in principle. In fact, even if one presumes that, in
voting, only political' beliefs and attitudes are relevant, it is hard to
discern any precise limits for such relevance. However, I could try to claim
that certain features of these ratings (namely the features whose expression
your method hinders or forbids) are irrelevant strategically', i.e. for
practical purposes of voting. Thus, as a pass-fail partisan I could claim
irrelevance of an intermediate grade between full pass and full fail; or, as
a partisan of strict-only ranking, I could claim irrelevance of equal grades
(e.g., the case of a first-place tie). A followon posting will consider
such claims.
DEGREE OF SINCERITY. The notion of sincerity' is not only absolute, but
relative, a matter of degree. As in the above examples, full or absolute
sincerity may at times be disallowed by the election method, but anyhow some
votes do seem more sincere' than do others. Enabling more sincere' voting
is certainly a major goal in our quest for better election methods.
Degree of sincerity can be quantified when, as above, one of the above-cited
election methods is used and moreover each voter's relevant beliefs are
taken to be expressible via a set of ratings. Using a suitable index of
distance or discrepancy, a vote's insincerity can be equated to the
calculated discrepancy between the actual vote and the nearest fully sincere
vote. (Actually casting the latter may well be disallowed by the election
method.) Mathematically there are various ways to define such an index. At
this point, preference for one index over another seems largely a subjective
matter.
SINCERE VOTE V. SINCERE EFFECT. All the above is just the start of the
sincerity' capers! For example, it is quite possible that a method allows
sincere VOTING but ensures insincere (or anyhow not fully sincere) SCORING
of the candidates. That is, at times there will be no change in scores if
some one voter's sincere vote be replaced by an insincere vote. Such is
exactly what happens in US presidential elections: change of a single vote
will in general not change the candidates' scores - namely their electoral
vote counts - which are used to decide the winner.
Election methods featured in this list's discussions suggest other
possibilities for deriving such insincere-scoring methods. In particular,
suppose that (as above) the relevant beliefs are taken to be fully expressed
via the voters' grade-ratings of the candidates, and that (as usual) a
candidate's score is got by summing his or her grades. To get a
sincere-voting-insincere-scoring method, just take each summed grade to be
not the actually marked raw' grade but a suitably transformed value.
For instance, transform each raw grade to 1 (pass) or 0 (fail) according as
the grade is at least c or not, where c is a desired criterion value
(between 0 and 1), say c=0.50. Or, transform each ballot's set of raw
grades to ranks.
THANKS FOR YOUR HEED. - Joe
_____________________________________________________________________________________
Get more from the Web. FREE MSN Explorer download : http://explorer.msn.com
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list