[EM] Proof idea that IRV can't be summable

Kristofer Munsterhjelm km_elmet at t-online.de
Tue Dec 1 14:25:37 PST 2020


Here's an idea that may be used to prove that any attempt to find a
clever way of making IRV summable (in a linear sense) will fail: that
it's not just the case that we haven't found such a solution, but that
it can't be done.

It's not a complete proof, but perhaps someone can complete it :-) And,
of course, it could be wrong; I could be missing something.

Consider a voting method as a union of convex polytopes expressed as
sets of linear inequalities. The unknown variables are the ballot
numbers: e.g. in the three-candidate no-truncation case, they're ABC,
ACB, BAC, BCA, CAB, CBA: the number of people who expressed each preference.

Then if the c!-dimensional vector is inside this union of convex
polytopes, A wins (if the union is called a win region); or A wins or
ties for first (if the union is called a win-or-tie region)[1]. As far
as summability is concerned, we can pick whichever is more convenient as
long as the difference between the win-and-tie region and the win region
is not of full dimensionality (which means that as the number of voters
approach infinity, the proportion of ties approach zero). This is, to my
knowledge, the case for IRV.

My strategy is to show that for (almost) any pair of ballot variables,
there exists some win region with some polytope with some inequality
that treats both ballot variables equally by scaling both equally; and
another that treats them differently (by scaling them by different
amounts).

The inequalities need not be in the same polytopes, since the argument
is that the inequality requires the method to distinguish between two
variables (or treat them equally); and thus that any summary must also
allow the method to do so. A violation of this will degrade at least one
of the win regions.

So, letting the two ballot variables be X and Y, the inequality that
treats X and Y equally proves that if IRV is summable, the sums can't
all have a term that amounts to (X-Y), because then the inequality in
question could not treat X and Y equally. The second case proves that if
IRV is summable, the sums can't all have a term that amounts to (X+Y),
because then the inequality can't treat X and Y differently.

If this can be proven for all pairs, then there must be c! different
summed variables (since no pair can be treated differently nor equally),
and since c! is not polynomial in c, we're done.

Now, to familiarize, consider the win region for A. For IRV, the union
is of the form (three candidate example given here):

"B is eliminated, A wins pairwise against C" or
"C is eliminated, A wins pairwise against B"

If either of these is true, then A wins with certainty; otherwise, A
does not. In this particular case, the inequalities of the first
constituent polytope look something like:

ABC + ACB - BAC - BCA > 0	(A outscores B in the first round)
ABC + ACB - CAB - CBA > 0	(A outscores C in the first round)
CAB + CBA - BAC - BCA > 0	(C outscores B in the first round)
ABC + ACB + BAC + BCA - CAB - CBA > 0	(A beats C pairwise)

So now take two ballot orders X and Y, but not so that Y is X reversed.

Let the set S_1 be the set of candidates that must be removed so that
the first candidate of X and Y match. Since Y isn't X reversed, this set
is at most two candidates smaller than the set of all candidates. Then X
and Y have a common factor in an inequality belonging to a polytope
where all the candidates of S_1 have been eliminated; because both X and
Y then count towards the first preferences of someone not in S_1, vs
someone else not in S_1.

Then let the set S_2 be the set of candidates that must be removed so
that the first candidate listed differs. Since X is not Y, the set is at
most two candidates smaller than the set of all candidates. Then,
similarly, in the scenario where the candidates in S_2 are all
eliminated, X counts towards someone's first preferences while Y counts
towards someone else's. So if cX is the candidate listed first on X
after the candidates in S_2 have been eliminated, then a polytope
dealing with cX's win region after the candidates in S_2 have been
eliminated will have a X + ... - Y - ... > 0 inequality.

The cases where Y is the exact reverse of X can't be treated this way,
but that's no problem as there are only O(c) of them anyway: hence these
being summable won't make IRV itself polynomially summable.



Caveat: I haven't shown that every pair of constituent polytopes for A's
win region is nonconvex as a whole, and that there are no redundant
inequalities (that each polytope's inequality matrix is full rank).

That's necessary to make sure the win region can't be reconstructed in a
way so that the tricky inequalities disappear. In other words, if I
don't do this, then the following "proof" for the non-summability of
Plurality would work:

A wins if one of the following is true (one polytope per inequality):
	for i = all 2^k subsets of ballots that begin in A
		for j = all 2^p subsets of ballots that don't
			e_i * x > e_j * x
for some numbers k and p; where x is the ballot vector, and e_i and e_j
are the indicator vectors for the respective sets.

Then one could claim that due to the superpolynomial amount of
inequalities, Plurality is non-summable. The flaw lies in that e.g. the
inequalities
	ABC > CBA
	ACB > CBA
are entirely subsumed by the inequality
	ABC + ACB > CAB + CBA.
So the method doesn't need to discriminate between two situations that
it seems like it needs to at first glance.

I would also, strictly speaking, need to show that (win or tie region) \
(win region) is not of full dimensionality; or deal with the win-or-tie
region directly.

Finally, I have a feeling there's some kind of more general matrix rank
argument hiding in there somewhere. Perhaps it could be used to show
just what kind of positional elimination systems are non-summable.
Borda-elimination is summable because you can get the Borda score from
the Condorcet matrix; why is it different? Are there any other systems
like it?

-km

[1] Note that these methods are deterministic. If there are any random
tiebreaks, they will have to be determined ahead of time. It's then
clear that some random tiebreaks may make an otherwise summable method
non-summable if they're "random enough".


More information about the Election-Methods mailing list