[EM] (3) Kristofer and Steve on MJ &IRVa vs. MAM

steve bosworth stevebosworth at hotmail.com
Sat Jun 11 09:04:53 PDT 2016


To Kristofer,

Thank you for your earlier than expected response and especially for putting me onto Majority Judgment (MJ).

MJ seems to be even a better system for electing a single-winner than my IRVa.  In different ways, each allows each citizen to express the intensity with which she supports or opposes each candidate and guarantees the election of a winner who is supported by an absolute majority.  However, in contrast to IRVa, MJ enables each citizen within the MJ winner’s majority to be a part of that majority purely as a result of her own judgments.  She would never have to rely on her IRVa first choice but eliminated candidate sequentially to transfer her ‘default vote’ to the remaining candidate he currently sees as the one mostly likely to represent him and her most faithfully, i.e. until a majority candidate is discovered.  Also, while both IRVa and MJ would seems to offer no practical opportunity for anyone to manipulate an election with many voters and candidates, theoretically MJ would seems to be even more resistant to strategic voting.

Do you agree?  Is MJ currently your own preferred method for electing a single-winner?

Your answers to these questions may help further to clarify any later discussion we may have both about IRVa and MAM.

________________________________________

From: Kristofer Munsterhjelm <km_elmet at t-online.de>

Sent: Wednesday, June 1, 2016 9:14 PM

To: steve bosworth; election-methods at lists.electorama.com

Subject: Re: [EM] Kristofer and Steve on IRVa vs. MAM

On 05/30/2016 04:53 PM, steve bosworth wrote:

> This reply to Kristofer's post is strengthened by the attachments it mentions and which Steve will also sent to you by email if you wish (stevebosworth at hotmail.com).

 ________________________________________

> From: steve bosworth <stevebosworth at hotmail.com>

> Sent: Sunday, May 29, 2016 7:54 PM

> To: Kristofer Munsterhjelm

> Subject: Re: Your 5th APR dialogue with Steve

> To Kristofer,

> Thank you for your response. In one sense, I accept that if

> truncated ballots are not permitted, Condorcet will also support the winner with

> at least by 50% + 1, e.g. the MAM winner will be supported by at least

> 50%+1 of all the voters. However, this ‘support’ will usually be

> composed mainly of indirect or ‘transitive’ support. In contrast to

> IRVa, the percentage of voters who have expressly preferred the winner

> over each of the other candidates can easily be much less than 50%. This

> is illustrated by the example discussed in the Endnote to the attached

> newly drafted Appendix 4 to my article (Super Equality for Each

> Citizen’s Vote in the Legislature’).

>

> In that extreme example, ‘as a result of using IRV, candidate F is

> elected with a 61% majority and with an average intensity of preference

> of 9.62 out of 10. In contrast, by counting the same 100 ballots using

> MAM, candidate E is elected with the explicit support of only 39% and

> with an average intensity of preference of 9.28.’



K: What is the definition of "average intensity of preference"?

I tend to think that it's generally impossible to directly infer

enthusiasm from a ranked ballot, since we're dealing with ordinal data.

All you can say is whether "X likes Y more than X likes Z".

S: Yes and I accept that ‘likes more’ does not always amount to ‘enthusiasm’.  However, it is always a ‘preference’.

K: You can't know whether a ballot like

A>B>C>D>E>F

is

"I really like A, B, and C; I think D and E are so-so, and I loathe F"

S: No, if this is what the voter feels, this is better expressed as

A=B=C>D=E

And leave F to be counted equal as ranked bottom with any other candidate not ‘expressly’ preferred.

K: or if it is

"I really like A, I think B is so-so, and I hate everybody else, but I'd

rather have C than D, D than E, E than F".

S:  Again, if ‘hate’ means ‘I do not want to support their election in any way, I see these feelings as more clearly expressed as follows:

A>B

However, if, in this case, ‘hate’ includes degrees of dislike, and the fear that F might only be prevented from being elected by the election of C, D, or E; this would be best expressed as:

A>B>C>D>E

K: In other words, the rankings themselves can't tell you whether

A>B>C>D

is

Washington > Lincoln > Bush > Khrushchev

or if it is

Lincoln > Khrushchev > Lenin > Stalin,

S:  A given voter herself knows.

K: … and how much weight you should put on first place compared with second

place is obviously different for these two scenarios, as far as

intensity is concerned.

S:  Nevertheless, each voter must decide.

K: The general approach for dealing with intensity of ranking is to use

ratings instead, or use something like Majority Judgement where you're

permitted to skip ranks and each rank has a name ("Excellent", "Good", etc).



As for the MAM example, it seems that F wins in MAM as well.



If I'm not mistaken, your vote set is



38: F

23: G>F

25: E

9: M>N>E

5: K>P>E



candidates: E F G K M N P



The Condorcet matrix (row beats column) is



Option  E       F       G       K       M       N       P

E       0       39      39      34      30      30      34

F       61      0       38      61      61      61      61

G       23      23      0       23      23      23      23

K       5       5       5       0       5       5       5

M       9       9       9       9       0       9       9

N       9       9       9       9       0       0       9

P       5       5       5       0       5       5       0



The wv matrix is



Option  E       F       G       K       M       N       P

E       0       0       39      34      30      30      34

F       61      0       38      61      61      61      61

G       0       0       0       23      23      23      23

K       0       0       0       0       0       0       5

M       0       0       0       9       0       9       9

N       0       0       0       9       0       0       9

P       0       0       0       0       0       0       0



So the first few lock-ins go (equal strength defeats broken in

alphabetical order for simplicity):



1. F>E with 61 votes

2. F>K with 61 votes

3. F>M with 61 votes

4. F>P with 61 votes



Clearly, E can't possibly beat F since F is locked ahead of E on the

very first step. You must have calculated the Condorcet or wv matrix

incorrectly. In fact, regardless of whether you use wv or margins, F

becomes the CW: he beats everybody else pairwise.



If you'd like to check the calculation for other ballot sets,

http://www.ericgorr.net/condorcet/ will give both the Condorcet matrix

and the wv matrix when verbosity is set to "Tell me some things" or

"Tell me everything".



It'll also show what pairs MAM locks if you set it to "Tell me

everything", although it may not show them in order of defeat strength;

it locks large numbers of pairs at once when it knows that it can do so

without causing a cycle.



I'll further comment on a few others, as much as I have time to at least:



> As a result, the attached appendix also claims that only ‘IRVa

> allows

> each citizen to guarantee:

> 1)      that her vote will continue quantitatively to count equally,



- As do all -a methods.



> 2) that the winner will be elected by a majority of all the voters

>    who have not deliberately cancelled the possibility of their otherwise

>    wasted ‘default vote’ being counted until the majority winner is

>    discovered, and



I'm not sure what that means.



> 3)      that the winner will be supported more enthusiastically than any other candidate.’



Consider this example from rangevoting.org:



10:     G > C > P > M

3:      C > G > P > M

5:      C > P > M > G

6:      M > P > C > G

4:      P > M > C > G



IRV elects M. But M only has 6 first preferences whereas C, the

Condorcet winner, has 8. Since C is the Condorcet winner, it's also

supported by a majority, so majority support can't be the reason C

doesn't win in IRV.

So if first preferences is the metric of enthusiasm, IRV fails.



And if it isn't, then it's possible to construct examples where:



        - some candidate A has one more first preference vote than some other

candidate W,

        - A has no second place preferences,

        - W has some constant c number of second place preferences,

        - A wins in IRV,

        - W is the Condorcet winner,



meaning that if one first place vote is worth x second place votes, then

you can make IRV choose wrong no matter what x is.



E.g. for x=14:



4:      W>B>A>C>D

5:      A>W>B>C>D

5:      C>W>A>B>D

5:      D>W>A>B>C



W has 4 first preferences and A has 5. W has 15 second preferences (A

has none) and A has 14 third preferences.



So either enthusiasm is only based on first preferences, in which case

the first example shows that IRV gets it wrong, or it's based on first

*and* second preferences, in which case the second example would make

IRV get it wrong.



There's a continuum argument hiding in here, though I don't have time to

go into it in detail. Briefly: IRV is more Plurality-like than Condorcet

and more Condorcetian than Plurality. So any argument that favors IRV

has to show that the argument can't be taken to its logical conclusion

to favor either Condorcet or Plurality just as strongly.



> S: Yes, if I understand you, this ‘incrementation’ can cause each

> citizen’s vote to have a different value in the whole process. If so,

> the principle of ‘one-citizen-one-vote’ is violated.



Suppose we conduct a presidential election by Approval ("thumbs up" or

"like") voting, and there are 5 candidates. That is, each voter gets a

list of the 5 presidential candidates and is told to place a mark by

each candidate he likes. The candidate with the most likes/approvals wins.



Now suppose that voter A chooses to approve of two candidates, while

voter B chooses to approve of three. Does that violate one citizen one

vote? After all, voter A "spent" two points (gave points to two

candidates) while B "spent" three.



I'd say no, because each ballot has one state for each candidate: either

liked or unliked. Each ballot adds the same information to the voting

pool: whether the candidate chose to strengthen candidate X, candidate

Y, candidate Z, etc... So if there are 5 candidates, each ballot has 5

aye/nay votes, and each voter spends 5 such votes. The voter who liked

two candidates used 2 ayes and 3 nays, and the other voter used 3 ayes

and 2 nays.



Analogously, a Condorcet election could be conducted by asking the voter

"in which of these runoffs would you support the first candidate on the

ballot?". There are n^2 hypothetical runoffs for n candidates, so that

kind of ballot would have n^2 aye/nay votes.



In a three candidate election, someone who votes



A>B>C



would say aye to "would you support the first candidate on the ballot in

an A vs B runoff?", "in an A vs C runoff?" and "in a B vs C runoff?",

and nay to all the others. It's just that, to spare the voter from

having to fill out a bunch of tedious yes/no questions, the method

infers the answer to these aye/nay questions from a ranked ballot.



And if the Approval ballot doesn't violate one man one vote, then

neither does the Condorcet ballot. Yes, some voters increment more

runoffs than others (if there's equal rank and truncation), but deciding

to *not* increment someone's runoff is also a vote.



>>he helps C more by protecting C from A and B, i.e. by increasing A>C and

>> A>B.

> I do not understand your phrase:  ‘i.e. by increasing A>C and A>B’.

> This is because C>A>B>D favors C over A.



Either I meant that he helps C by protecting C from an increase of A>C

and from an increase of A>B, or that was a typo. In either case, what I

meant was that if someone raises C, the number of votes it takes to make

A beat C is also increased.



I could probably have made that clearer.



> S: Using IRVa in the example in the attached Endnote, and when also

> used in your following example, each vote continues to count (directly

> or indirectly) as one until a majority winner is discovered.



Monotonicity failures require multiple ballot sets. See

http://www.rangevoting.org/Monotone.html. My point is that the voter's

power is an unpredictable function of his ranking. If he moves a

candidate higher on his ranking, he may cause the candidate to lose and

vice versa. That's not something that says "equal power" to me.



Under no method (except possibly Random Pair, Random Dictator, and

combinations of them) are votes completely equal in power anyway. It

depends on what they vote and when they do it. Suppose you have a

majority election:



51: A

50: B



and two voters show up, and they're the last two voters of the election.

If they vote for B, they change the outcome (great power); if they vote

for A, nothing happens (not so much).



>> K: * That is, unless there are truncated ballots, but then IRV doesn't give

>> a majority either.

> This is why I added ‘Asset Voting’ to IRV, to produce IRVa.



Yes, but we were initially talking about IRV without -a:



>>> However, before I do that, I want to claim that in comparison to all

>>> other electoral system not using the above asset voting, APR (also

>>> without this asset addition) still does all it could do to allow each

>>> citizen to guarantee that her one vote will be added to the weighted

>>> vote of the one elected candidate of all the pre-established number of

>>> the assembly’s members whom she most trusts to speak, work, and vote

>>> faithfully on her behalf. Do you agree? Also in this case, this

>>> simplified APR might waste some votes.



That's what I was responding to.
-------------- next part --------------
An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
URL: <http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/attachments/20160611/6ef6fca1/attachment-0001.htm>


More information about the Election-Methods mailing list