[EM] Comparing CW with "write-in pairwise" CW
Kevin Venzke
stepjak at yahoo.fr
Wed Oct 30 15:46:10 PDT 2013
Hi Kristofer,
----- Mail original -----
> De : Kristofer Munsterhjelm <km_elmet at t-online.de>
>>
>> To take a step back: Why regard pairwise contests at all? To my mind,
>> what they can simulate is a test of whether supporters of one
>> candidate feel cheated when the other candidate is elected. In the
>> case of B vs. C we want to know whether we can elect one of those two
>> without irritating the supporters of the other. The answer is: the
>> election of one or the other gives neither side a strong reason to
>> complain.
>
> Methods like River have another idea of what to do: they say that "okay,
> there may be complaints, but our criteria state that there's always a
> counter-argument that is stronger if you consider pairwise data and
> paths alone". More specifically, that if A-supporters say that A should
> have won instead of B, because X beats B and is beaten by A, then the
> B-supporters can say that there also exists an Y that beats A and is
> beaten by B, and Y beats A more strongly than X beats B.
>
Yes, in practice River etc. are good. But the actual logic or interpretation of the pairwise contests doesn't have a clear tie to the "big picture." In other words I fear we can have a long philosophical discussion on the methods and aesthetics of tracing beatpaths and thereby miss the forest for the trees, within a given scenario. Ultimately you have voters who regret the way they voted or would be happier had their candidate not run, and that's the key thing in my view.
> My own ideas about Condorcet is more that it is a good default balance
> between strategy and honest results, if it is given that we only have
> ranks to work with. The strategy resistance is related to a mean-median
> link where Borda is to the mean rank as Condorcet is to the median rank.
> The honesty aspect is related to that the CW is the one who can win any
> runoff assuming that nobody changes his mind. In itself, it's an
> intuitive generalization of majority rule, and one could also use
> generalizations of the Condorcet Jury Theorem to more formally argue in
> that direction -- or observations like Kemeny being a max-likelihood
> estimator under certain models of noise on the ballots.
>
Yes, I think you can justify Condorcet via analogies like these or others. But I think it's frighteningly easy to find yourself discussing abstract fantasy at the very first step.
>
>> The second type of disagreement, the other 30%, is the case where
>> Condorcet picks a single winner while WICW picks *two* possible
>> winners: 42 A 30 B>C 28 C>B
>>
>> Here we have a mutual majority and a CW, but WICW is indecisive. The
>> B>C pairwise win isn't counted, because once the majority splits up
>> between B and C camps, neither can contend with the A>{B,C} voters.
>> This is quite an oddity and I'm not sure what to make of it.
>>
>> Does it suggest any actual insights? I kind of think it does: While B
>> is unambiguously the superior candidate, it isn't by much. It's
> quite
>> possible that if we forcibly extracted second preferences from the A
>> voters, that they would prefer C. It's unknown, it may matter, and
>> WICW says as much.
>>
>> Furthermore, there should be no shame in being indecisive,
>> considering that Condorcet is often indecisive as well.
>
> Couldn't this be fixed by a Smith intersect WICW method? I guess that
> would feel a bit like a hack, though, and may induce what I call
> discontinuities, thus breaking certain types of criterion compliance.
>
Yes to all that. I suspect the WICW method itself would have some discontinuities already.
> Or if you think there's real indecision here in the people, and the
> methods are just mirroring that, you could hold a runoff among the
> candidates in the more indecisive set (WICW and Smith respectively).
>
You could. It's not that I think there is actually indecision (or rather: it's not that I think it would actually be helpful to judge this as indecision) but that I'm trying to insist on a specific principle (that the winner should be somebody who might win if all voters were maximally informed and strategic), and I don't think that principle has a single selection here. I suspect it can't.
>
>> On the other hand, I could easily believe that this result is
>> indicative of a need for a "second draft" of the concept, that
>> wouldn't suffer from this problem. One thing you could easily do is
>> remove non-winners and then refigure WICW's result. But that takes it
>> further from the original idea and the justification becomes cloudy.
>
> That's also possible, yes, but I do agree with you that elimination
> feels kludgy.
>
>
>> I should say, my point isn't really to define a new criterion (and
>> less still, a method). It's more that I want to define a model that
>> matches the logic or aesthetic that I tend to use when evaluating
>> scenarios.
>
> I see that point. It is good to quantify what one thinks is aesthetic or
> right... although at this point, we may be getting to kind of the
> opposite problem - that we have so many criteria, aesthetics, and models
> to choose between that it's hard to know which one models how people
> act, or which one is most appropriate for an accurate election method.
>
I would describe the situation differently. For myself, I use three different criteria (SDSC, SFC, and Plurality) that I view as facets of this exact paradigm that I'm trying to put words to. It's an effort to consolidate, not just add to the pile. There are a lot of criteria out there but I'm not sure there are so many underlying paradigms to aid in picking from them.
Kevin Venzke
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list