[EM] Correspondences between PR and lottery methods (was Centrist vs. non-Centrists, etc.)
fsimmons at pcc.edu
fsimmons at pcc.edu
Wed Jul 20 11:35:17 PDT 2011
From: Andy Jennings
> On Mon, Jul 18, 2011 at 6:00 PM, wrote:
>
> > Andy and I were thinking mostly of Party Lists via RRV. His
> question was
> > that if we used RRV, either
> > sequential or not, would we get the same result as the
> Ultimate Lottery
> > Maximization. I was able to
> > show to our satisfaction, that at least in the non-sequential
> RRV version,
> > the results would be the
> > same. It seems like the initial differences between
> sequential and
> > non-sequential RRV would disappear
> > in the limit as the number of candidates to be seated
> approached infinity.
> >
> > Would that imply P=NP? In other words, sequential RRV might
> be an
> > efficient method of
> > approximating a solution (for large n) of non-sequential RRV
> (which is
> > undoubtedly NP hard). What
> > would be analogous in the Traveling Salesman Problem? Don't
> hold your
> > breath, but it would be
> > interesting to sort out the analogy, if possible.
> >
>
>
> I am still hopeful that sequential RRV with a large number of
> seats, leaving
> each candidate in as if they were their own party, would be a
> good and
> tractable way to choose legislators and give them each a
> different amount of
> "voting power". I'm hoping it would be possible to calculate the
> proportions in the limit as n goes to infinity.
>
> But sequential RRV is completely ignorant about how many seats
> need to be
> filled, so it's not really going to find the globally optimum N-winner
> representative body like ULM and non-sequential RRV aim to do. This
> "infinite sequential RRV" might be good when there is no pre-
> determinednumber of seats to fill but instead we want the method
> to choose the number
> of winners. For real elections, however, I suspect that it will
> give some
> voting power to every candidate, so maybe it's not that good for
> choosing a
> representative body.
Good points!
>
> Here's an example, on the other hand, where this method chooses
> too few
> winners:
> 10 voters approve A and C
> 10 voters approve A and D
> 10 voters approve A and E
> 10 voters approve B and C
> 10 voters approve B and D
> 10 voters approve B and E
>
> If you're choosing two winners, I think the obvious winners are
> A and B.
> But if you want to choose three winners, I think the obvious
> choice is C,
> D, and E. Only a method that knows how many winners you're
> going to choose
> can make the correct decision here. In this case, RRV will
> choose A and B.
> If A and B are "left in" (pretending they are parties even if
> they are
> candidates) then RRV will continue to alternate between A and B.
> In the
> limit, it will give half of the voting power to A and half to B.
> This is
> just not helpful if you wanted to choose three winners.
I would like to point out that if the election were single winner, this RRV result of 50%A+50%B would be
the closest thing to a consensus lottery. In other words, your method of using RRV with repetition is a
great way of generating proportional lotteries. So it seems that good lotteries are easier to generate
than good PR results.
>
> ULM and non-sequential RRV evaluate each possible combination of
> winners and
> can do the right thing in the three winner case.
If I am thinking straight, PAV would give the same max score of
20*(1+1/2)+40
to three slates of three candidates {A, B, C}, {A, B, D}, and {A, B, E}.
If higher resolution range values were available, non-sequential PAV would probably favor one of these
three.
This reminds me of "envy free" versus merely fair division. The {C, D, E} slate would be "envy free" as
well as fair, even though {A, B, C} would give more total satisfaction, while still being fair in the sense
that each voter got at least the satisfaction guaranteed by PR. In the case of {A, B, C} the D and E
voters might well envy the extra satisfaction of the C voters.
>
> Andy
>
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list