[EM] DYN
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
abd at lomaxdesign.com
Mon Apr 5 08:40:40 PDT 2010
At 07:51 PM 4/4/2010, fsimmons at pcc.edu wrote:
>I waould like to advertise Delegable Yes No (DYN) voting again. It
>overcomes the main difficulty with Approval, which is that the
>common voter will will not feel sure about approving or disapproving
>some of the candidates.
Well, that's not the main difficulty with approval, that's the main
difficulty with *elections*, as Dodgson noted in abou 1884. The Asset
Voting solution, which this is a restricted version of, is the only
solution I've seen that doesn't involve going back to the voters.
>Under DYN you check Y next to all of the candidates that you are
>sure that you want to approve (like your favorite), you check N next
>to all of the candidates that you are sure that you disapprove (like
>the candidate you most detest), you leave blank the choices for the
>candidates you are not sure about, and you circle the name of the
>approved candidate that you want to delegate the remaining Y/N decisions to.
Or there is a separate check box for that.
Can we imagine someone who wants to delegate the remaining decisions
to, but who doesn't approve the candidate for the office? Interesting
conditions that would take. "I trust this person to choose who will
make the decisions, but not to make the decisions." In the office,
the person can get advice. In a sensible system, they could name a
proxy to actually make decisions, and, in any case, many legislators
and office-holders do functionally delegate much or most work, even
though they still have to sign off on it.
>After the sure Y/N votes are counted, the candidates make their
>proxy votes for their supporters on the delegated choices. The
>partial talleys already available to them help to counteract
>disinformation from the media.
The candidates, generally, will be far more informed about the other
candidates than the media. Problem is, the media can influence those
No votes. In other words, the voters, under media influence, may
restrict their trusted candidate, not allowing him or her to make the
best decision in their interest. I prefer pure Asset Voting, and I
prefer that it be used for accurate proportional representation of
the voters' trust, and that elections, then, be done as parliamentary
process, for terms at the pleasure of the assembly. Majority rule.
Asset Voting can, in fact, function similarly to Yes/No voting, if we
understand that any voter who does not want to fully delegate voting
power can become a "candidate" and vote for himself or herself, thus
obtaining the right to vote in the final processes.
I call the set of those who hold votes to distribute or use in a
determinative asset election the "electoral college," and, because
they are public voters, they can be enabled to actually vote in the
resulting assembly. Asset can become far more than a voting system, a
method of election. It can become a hybrid representative/direct
democracy. The restriction necessary because of the scale is that
participation in *deliberation* in the assembly is restritcted to
those who hold seats. In a sense, then, for most electors the issue
will become the choice of an effective proxy, with the ability
remaining to effectively cancel the vote of the proxy by voting
directly. My sense is that direct voting would be relatively rare,
once the enormous freedom of being able to choose representation
rather than elect it is realized.
>This is one way to solve the problem
>
>49 C
>
>26 A>B
>
>25 B>A
>
>Where the 25 threaten to bullet B.
And why would they do that? And, indeed, what is the best outcome of
this election? Without some idea of preference strengths, it's not
really visible. It is obvious that we have a 51:49 majority, very
thin, who prefer either of A or B to C. The Condorcet winner is A.
But this could easily be a situation where the Condorcet Criterion
violates maximized social utility.
Suppose these are the absolute utilities, but normalized to the
candidate set over all voters. (Not individually). Define utility as
the *actual* pleasure/pain response of each voter to the election of
a candidate, as viewed by our omniscient observer. If election had a
dollar value to voters, and voters had equal ability to pay, the
difference between the utility of two candidates would be what the
voter would consider break-even (any lower cost would be a bargain,
any higher cost would be a loss).
49: A 00, B 40, C 100 (These utilities for C and A define the scale)
26: A 70, B 60, C 50
25: A 60, B 70, C 50
Just for fun, consider that 50 is, in this case, indifference, the
candidate causes neither pain nor pleasure.
mean: A 33.2, B 52.7, C 74.5.
Does this predict the votes shown? Yes. The C voters do not approve
of either A or B. In Bucklin, this is how they might vote. Except
that it's a naive vote, if this is single-round deterministic. I'll
get to that. They would also circle C.
The A and B voters have the preferences indicated, and, because of
the restricted choices, are not likely to vote for C, even though
they approve of C (minimally, I include indifference under absolute approval).
The A and B voters do not have strong preference. They, in fact,
would accept the election of C. It is clear from the utilities
assumed that the best winner is the candidate who would win under
Plurality. This is why I suggest, strongly, that voting systems
theorists start to work with utility profiles, because preference
order tells us way too little to make sense of voter behavior, and we
cannot understand the value of an election without that information.
The Condorcet and Majority criteria are deficient, understood naively.
In a real election, if the profile is of the overall eligible
electorate, and if this is a special election, not mixed with other
elections, the C voters would turn out to vote preferentially, thus
electing C straightaway. Thus we can also see how comupulsory voting
prevents an important function of voting process, the test of
preference strength that allows simple voting systems to perform much
better than preference analysis would indicate. In real deliberative
process, when voters don't have significant preference, they abstain,
as long as either outcome is acceptable to them.
With DYN, it is possible that the A and B voters will not vote No on
A. After all, they don't have strong feelings *against* this
candidate. The C voters, however, will definitely vote No on A, and
might vote No on B.
Suppose they vote No on A, but the A and B voters do not vote No on
C. This leaves us with 49 % for C, 26% for A, and 25% for B. B will
win, because at this point there are three voters (A, B, and C), and
they each know the voting power, and C is constrained to vote either
for self or for B. A runoff would be between C and A. C would win a
runoff, I'd predict from the utilities, because of differential turnout.
Unstated was how the proxies would vote, and using what method.
Let me look at this election as Bucklin. I'd suggest that this would
be the likely Bucklin ballots:
49: C
26: A>B>?
25: B>A>?
If this is a majority-required election, i.e., Bucklin is used as a
primary with a runoff if needed, some percentage of the A and B
voters will rationally add a third preference for C, because they
would prefer or be indifferent to the election of C to the cost of a
runoff. If more than 1% of them do this, C wins. Otherwise there is a
runoff between C and A, I'd assume. A is the Condorcet winner, so, by
the runoff rules I've proposed, there is no exception there. The
runoff tests preference strength; that's why C wins. And that is the
utility-maximizing outcome, minimizing regret, and, in fact, given
the utility profile, nobody regrets the election at all.
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list