[EM] Some Approval strategies
Michael Ossipoff
mikeo2106 at msn.com
Fri Jul 20 05:09:43 PDT 2007
WS, in his paper,mentioned a strategy that Rob LeGrand calls Strategy A, and
which I call BF-Certain.
"BF" stands for "Best Frontrunner".
I'll get to this more, soon, but, for voting in an Approval election, that
strategy is only any good if it's fairly certain which of the two expected
frontrunners will outpoll the other. Maybe sometimes you know that the
biggest votegetter will, more likely than not, outpoll the runner-up, in the
next election. But you mgiht not know how probable that is. Is it a sure
thing, or is he just barely more likely to outpoll? That's also the
situation for the simulated voters who use previous vote totals to inform
their strategy in a simulated series of Approval elections.
BF-Uncertain (to be defined below) is optimal for the extreme case when you
have no idea which frontrunner will outpoll the other. Then, of course,
BF-Uncertain is a much better choice than BF-Certain.
But, when you don't know how likely it is that the biggest votegetter will
outpoll the runner-up in the next election, and if you had to choose
BF-Certain or BF-Uncertain, which would be better?
BF-Uncertain would be much better. That's because BF-Certain is optimal only
under the conditions under which your vote has the smallest probability of
influencing the election--when it's nearly certain which candidate will win.
I've been talking about these BF strategies without defining them.
What they all have in common is their assumption that it's nearly certain
that the winner will be one of the two expected frontrunners (determined
maybe by the previous election's vote totals, or from polls, if you trust
the polls--a big "if"). So, in their voting, what they all have in common
is: Vote for the frontrunner you like better, and don't vote for the other
frontrunner. Also, vote for everyone you like better than the frontrunner
you like better. (That last sentence is for the tiny chance that someone
other else could be in a tie or near-tie with a frontrunner. Of course,
also, it's desirable to show support for the best candidates).
Where they differ is in which, if any, of the "inbetween candidates" you
vote for. The inbetween candidates are the candidates whose merit is between
those of the two frontrunners.
Why vote for inbetweens at all, or for anyone other than your favorite
frontrunner, if it's certain that one of the frontrunners will win? I said
only that it's _nearly_ certain that one of the two frontrunners will win.
The important thing is voting for your preferred frontrunner and not for the
other. From BF's main assumption, it's nearly irrelevant whether you vote
for an inbetween. But, as a refinement, one can vote for some inbetweens
just for the tiny chance that one of them might be in a tie or near-tie with
one of the frontrunners.
That's why there are several BF versions.
Of course, since the inbetweens matter so little, there's nothing wrong with
this advice to voters:
Vote for whichever frontrunner you like better than the other, and for
everyone better than hir. Or, which almost amounts to the same thing, vote
for the candidate you'd vote for in Plurality, and for everyone better than
hir. The first of those could be called BF-Plain, and the 2nd could be
called Plurality-And-Better. They're probably the best BF versions to offer
the public.
Now to define the other BF versions, in terms of votes for inbetweens:
BF-Certain:
If your favorite frontrunner is the one almost sure to outpoll the other,
then don't vote for any inbetweens. If your less-favorite frontrunner is the
one almost sure to outpoll the other, then vote for all the inbetweens.
(This is equivalent to the strategy that WS described, and that Rob LeGrand
calls Strategy A, except that it's defined when the two frontrunners have
polled equally, and there's no top votegetter).
BF-Certain is optimal when it's certain which frontrunner will outpoll the
other.
BF-Uncertain:
Vote for all the inbetweens whose merit is better than the mean of the two
frontrunners.
That can be shown to be optimal when you have no information about which
frontrunner will outpoll the other.
BF-Intermediate:
Use an Approval cutoff halfway between those that would be recommended by
BF-Certain and BF-Uncertain. It could be argued that this minimizes how far
off your Approval cutoff can be from where it should be. But, because
BF-Certain is optimal when your vote counts the least, there's a case for
saying that BF-Uncertain, or something closer to it would be better. Maybe,
when all you know is that your favorite frontrunner's probability of
outpolling the other frontrunner is not 0 or 1 or .5 (it isn't .5, because
he's ahead or behind in the polls), the best place for the Approval cutoff
is somewhere between BF-Intermediate and BF-Uncertain.
BF-Probability:
Say you have an estimate of the probability that your favorite frontrunner
will outpoll the other. I'll call that probabililty Px.
It can be shown that, then, it's optimal to vote for all the inbetweens
whose merit is Px of the way from that of the worse frontrunner to the
better frontrunner. In other words, say you feel that Px is .67 There's .67
probability that your favorite frontrunner will outpoll the other. Then vote
for all the inbetweens whose merit is at least 67% of the way from that of
the worse frontrunner to that of the better frontrunner.
Px could be estimated, or it could be calculated based on the typical
dispersion of candidates' vote totals in previous elections, and the
difference between the frontrunners' vote totals in the previous election.
Or, alternatively, maybe a table of Px estimates could be prepared from a
simulation. The applicability of the simulation to actual conditions would
of course be very questionable, but it might be better than nothing.
Likewise, a simulation might be used to estimate where the Approval cutoff
should be positioned between that of BF-Uncertain and BF-Intermediate.
The BF strategies are good when you have evidence or a feel for who the
frontrunners are. When you don't, you could use the Better-Than-Expectation
strategy:
Vote for each candidate who is so good that you'd rather have hir in office
than hold the election.
(In other words, vote for everyone who is better than your expectation for
the election).
That's been shown to be optimal given certain fairly reasonable assumptions.
At least two different sets of assumptinos lead to that strategy, giving it
extra confirmation. i posted about that around February of 2005.
But I emphasize that usually you'll know who deserves your approval and who
doesn't. Rarely would you need these strategies. Who is good enough,
deserving enough, honest enough? Or who do you just feel you need to
compromise down to? The strategies described above are only for when you
don't have such a feel. Maybe unfamiliar candidates or unimportant election.
Or maybe the strategies could help suggest the right vote configuration for
the participants in the co-operation-defection dilemma that I'll post about
soon. The co-operation-defection dilemma is probably the nearest thing to a
problem for Approval, but I tell why i claim that it isn't a problem.
Mike Ossipoff
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list