[EM] Saari reply
Blake Cretney
blake at condorcet.org
Sun Jun 23 16:17:17 PDT 2002
On Thu, 2002-06-20 at 13:45, Tarr, Adam wrote:
> Dave wrote:
>
> > I missed any believable proof of this equivalence.
> >
I'm going to give an outline of a proof, where I make various
simplifying assumptions, but I think the main issue will be resolved,
and it will be clear how to deal with more complicated situations.
First, I am going to restrict myself to 3 candidates. Only two will be
front-runners, but I have no idea which (in fact all cases will be
assumed equally likely).
Now, let's label the three candidates A,B,C. Without loss of
generality, A is my favourite, C is my least favourite, and B is in
between. I'm going to use a scale for utility where A's utility is 1
and C's is 0. B's is utility is assigned to the variable u. Also, I'm
going to assume that u>.5. The corresponding argument for u<.5 should
be obvious from my proof. The ballot will also allow the voter to
assign any rating between 0 and 1 inclusive.
So, obviously I should rate A at 1 and C at 0, and the only question is
how I should rate B. It would seem I should rate B at u, so I'm going
to try to prove that this is false. I'm going to argue that the
expected utility from rating B at 1 is higher. You might have other
ideas for how B should be rated, but for now I am only going to argue
against the B=u rating.
If the front-runner situation is A vs. C, it doesn't matter how I rate
B, so I will ignore this possibility. There are two remaining
possibilities: A vs. B and B vs. C. The vote of B=1 is obviously more
likely to cause B to win over C, but sacrifices the possibility of
causing A to win over B.
A plausible assumption (which I could defend in more detail) is that for
a large electorate, the probability of a difference in rating causing a
difference in outcome is proportionate to the size in the difference of
rating. I am using p as the chance of a full rating difference causing
a change. Of course, p is unknown, but between 0 and 1. But it
follows, for example, that a ratings difference of u, has a p*u chance
of having an effect, based on the assumption that the chance of a change
in outcome is proportional to the ratings difference.
B=u:
p*(1-u)*(1-u)[for A vs. B]
+ p*u*u [for B vs. C]
-------------
2
B=1:
p*0*(1-u) [for A vs. B]
+p*1*u [for B vs. C]
------
2
So, we get averages of
B=u:
(p*(1-u)*(1-u)+p*u*u)/2
p*(1-2u+u^2+u^2)/2
p*(1-2u+2u^2)/2
B=1: p*u/2
So, which is greater? Well remember that u<1, so u-1<0. Also, recall
that u>.5
u>.5
.5<u
1<2u
u-1 > 2*u*(u-1) [u-1<0]
u-1 > 2u^2-2u
u> 1-2u+2u^2
p*u/2 > p*(1-2u+2u^2)/2 [p>0]
So, the expected utility benefit of the B=1 strategy is higher than the
B=u strategy.
---
Blake Cretney
----
For more information about this list (subscribe, unsubscribe, FAQ, etc),
please see http://www.eskimo.com/~robla/em
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list