The "problem" with circularity (was Re: Reply to Blake Cretney)
Steve Eppley
SEppley at alumni.caltech.edu
Wed Feb 24 13:21:35 PST 1999
Blake Cretney has been doing a fine job replying to Donald Davison's
musings about circularity, but I have a few words I'd like to add:
Donald Davison wrote:
> It would be nice if Condorcet did not have those circular
> ties. Maybe something can be done to eliminate them.
-snip-
The circular ties in some Condorcetian methods (but not in plain
Condorcet!) correspond exactly to the voters' circular preferences
which they expressed in their preference order ballots. They are an
attribute of the voters, not of the voting method. One can't
eliminate voters' preferences (unless we lobotomize voters)! All one
can do is ignore their preferences, which wouldn't be as democratic
as tallying them.
I advise Blake to use the terminology "voters' circular preferences"
rather than Donald's "circular ties" to make it clearer that
circularity, when it occurs, is an attribute of the voters and not an
artifact of some methods.
Most people who have considered these issues have concluded that the
winner should always be one of the candidates in the top cycle. (See
definition below.) Whenever an organization uses the voting method
recommended by Robert's Rules of Order or something similar, one of
the top cycle is elected. Since most voting is done with such
methods, it's fair to say that most voting already satisfies the top
cycle criterion and what we're trying to do is modernize our
primitive public election methods so they also satisfy it.
Better methods, satisfying the top cycle criterion, have been used in
assemblies and not in public elections because given primitive
technology they are practical in assemblies but not in large public
elections. The marginal cost of repeated rounds of voting is small
in assemblies but large in public elections. What has now changed is
that the invention of machine-readable ballots--punch cards, etc.--
have made better methods practical in large public elections. (The
most important criterion is Feasibility, and what is feasible changes
with technological advances.)
Top Cycle: the smallest, non-empty subset of alternatives such
that every alternative in the subset "defeats pairwise" every
alternative not in the subset. (It is sometimes called the
Smith set, and it could be called the "dominant candidates.")
"Defeats Pairwise": Alternative X defeats pairwise alternative Y
when more voters ranked Y ahead of X than ranked X ahead of Y.
Given that the winner ought to be one of the top cycle, then when the
top cycle includes only one candidate--not really a cycle--that one
should be the winner. When the top cycle includes only one, that one
is often called the "Condorcet winner."
The "problem" to which Donald alluded is to decide which one of the
top cycle should be elected when the top cycle has more than one,
which happens when the voters have circular preferences regarding
three or more of the dominant candidates. (In theory non-circular
ties can also happen when vote counts match exactly, but as with
existing methods that kind of tie would be extremely rare.)
I think it's much less important, and not really valid, to try to
identify which one of the top cycle is "best" as long as one of them
gets elected. (Recall the discussion about the merits of the
Smith//Random method.) It's far more important to use a voting
method which minimizes incentives for voters to strategize, for
potential candidates to not compete, and for parties to want to
nominate only one candidate. If it minimizes those incentives, it
will also elect one of the top cycle.
Of course, such a method also needs to be understandable to curious
voters. *That* is our real problem, given the poor state of our
nation's education system. In my opinion, "pairwise comparison
principles" should be part of the public school curriculum; then it
would be easy to adopt the best election methods.
> We are justified in reducing the lower choices because the voters
> themselves value the lower choices less than their most preferred choice.
-snip-
Donald has apparently confused "utility" with "utility differences."
(An "absolute" with a "relative.") A preference is a comparison
between two alternatives. The expression "I like Ike" really means
"I prefer Ike to Adlai." Support and opposition are relative.
Just because a voter prefers a favorite (A) more than a compromise
(B) does NOT mean his/her relative preference for B rather than C is
in some way weaker than other voters' preference for B rather than C.
It's possible for the "B>C" preference of an ABC voter to be just as
strong as, or stronger than, the "B>C" preference of a BAC voter.
Here's an example to illustrate, where for convenience the voters'
utilities are expressed in dollars:
Voter 1's evaluations of the candidates' utilities:
A = +$1.5 billion
B = +$1 billion
C = -$1 billion
Voter 2's evaluations of the candidates' utilities:
A = +$0.5 billion
B = +$1 billion
C = -$1 billion
Note that both voters evaluate B and C identically. The
difference between utilities is what matters; that difference
is B-C = $2 billion. Therefore both voters will have identical
B>C preference intensities. (It would have been just as easy
to provide an example where the BAC voter's B>C preference is
counter-intuitively smaller than the ABC voter's B>C preference,
simply by having voter 2 rate C = -$0.5 billion.)
Information about the strength of voters' preferences is entirely
lacking from preference order ballots. One should avoid the urge to
jump to "intuitive" conclusions about other meanings "inferrable"
from an order of preference. Preferences are relative, not absolute,
and rankings contain no information about preference intensities.
(Sadly, methods which ask voters to express their intensities or
utility differences invariably create strong incentives for voters to
exaggerate.)
One thing we can say for sure is that a voter whose preference order
is ABC wants to be able to vote ABC and have that counted as a full
strength vote for B over C when that's needed to defeat C. What
happens if a system (like plain IRV) doesn't allow the voters to
reliably do that? It will deter candidates from competing, it will
cause each party to want to nominate only one candidate, and it will
cause voters like the above to insincerely rank B ahead of A whenever
it appears that B and C are both electable, A is probably not, and B
could be knocked out of contention if they fail to rank B ahead of A.
It will often backfire when the voters and potential candidates lack
the info about which ones are electable, as is the case in U.S. local
non-partisan elections where plain Instant Runoff is currently being
promoted.
So the method needs to count those relative preferences about
"lesser" candidates fully, when the voter needs them counted fully.
We already know that given a "select only one candidate" method, most
voters are willing to cast their vote for the "compromise" B in order
to defeat a "greater evil" C. The problem people have with
compromising is that they hate to compromise when compromise is
unnecessary. They have no problem compromising when they see that's
needed to prevent an even worse outcome. Flawed systems make it hard
or impossible to know when and to what extent compromise is
necessary, and thus facilitate special interest minorities getting
their way when a majority prefers something else. Good systems make
compromise (and majority electoral coalitions) automatic.
As Blake pointed out, IRV advocates make a big deal about the fact
that IRV guarantees that ranking a second choice can never help
defeat one's first choice. They gloss over the fact that ranking a
first choice ahead of one's second can easily help elect one's third
or worse choice, and that to compensate for this flaw the two big
parties will need to continue nominating only one candidate. The two
parties will continue to nominate using a wealth-driven primary
system, with a tendency to nominate off-center candidates due to the
higher primary turnout of party activists and the disenfranchisement
of independent voters in most states' primaries. That means the
outcomes will be the same with IRV as we already have in our partisan
elections, and the two big parties will remain entrenched. It will
offer (bogus) evidence that there's no need for more than two
parties. As Gary Cox pointed out in his book _Making Elections
Count_, Instant Runoff obeys Duverger's Law (which says that the two-
party system is caused by the voting method).
Perhaps Donald no longer advocates Instant Runoff, which is suggested
by his search for a noncircular method which satisfies the Condorcet
criterion. It should be pointed out that what Instant Runoff does
with the voters' less-preferred candidates isn't consistent:
sometimes it gives zero weight to them, then it may give full weight
to them, as if magically the voter switched from zero support to full
support. One wonders what they mean by "support" when they claim
that Instant Runoff elects candidates with more support.
> Condorcet has as many as one third circular ties.
-snip-
Actually, they can occur more often than that. The more candidates
competing to be in the center (which is where they'd try to be if
they want to be elected, given a system which elects centrists and
defeats minority wings) the greater is the chance that voters'
preferences will be circular. Also, the more voters there are, the
greater is the chance their preferences will be circular.
Peter Ordeshook's book _Game Theory and Political Theory_ provides a
table showing the probability of circularity as a function of the
number of voters and the number of alternatives. He notes that the
probability apparently goes to 100% as the number of voters and
alternatives both go to infinity.
What does it matter if the voters' preferences are frequently
circular? It's actually a good sign, in my opinion, because it
indicates that a lot of electable alternatives are competing and
therefore give the voters an opportunity to express their most
important relative preferences.
> If this theory proves to be true, the gain for the pairwise
> people would be great - no circular ties.
-snip-
More precisely: We would gain by not having to market to poorly
educated voters a procedure which is defined using language which is
potentially more complex (but not necessarily more complex) than some
other methods.
We've seen several reasonably good methods (better than Instant
Runoff) which don't use the language of circularity. Plain Condorcet
is one, Regular-Champion is another. Both of these are mentioned in
greater detail below. (Borda is yet another method free of the
language of circularity, but given Borda voters would learn to use a
"turkey-raising" offensive reversal strategy and would also have an
incentive to defensively downrank their favorites.)
My humble offering is to move the complexity out of the method, into
the laps of the dominant or near-dominant candidates (or the laps of
the sponsors of dominant ballot propositions, when we vote on rival
propositions). Simply precede Instant Runoff (or plain Condorcet)
with two simple steps:
1. After the voters cast their preference order ballots, publish
the preference orders (electronically, on the internet).
2. After step 1 is performed, allow candidates a short period of
time (perhaps a week) to voluntarily withdraw from contention
before the final result is tallied. (No candidate can be
forced to be a spoiler.)
3. Tally the preference orders using Instant Runoff (or plain
Condorcet), ignoring rankings of the withdrawn candidates.
To use Bruce Anderson's syntax, this method is named JITW//IRV (or
JITW//Condorcet). JITW stands for "just-in-time withdrawal."
I mention JITW//IRV before JITW//Condorcet because JITW//IRV is a
reasonable compromise which can be struck with IRV advocates. It
satisfies the criteria stated by IRV advocates at least as well as
plain IRV, and satisfies the criteria of pairwise advocates, without
adding significantly to the complexity of the IRV description.
I don't think there can be any serious argument against step 1,
regardless of the overall system, wherever ballots are machine-
readable. It would allow the performance of the system to be better
analyzed. It would provide more information about the voters'
preferences, which is the point of having people vote. The omission
of this step is a significant oversight in the IRV initiatives
currently being promoted. In the context of JITW, the ballot
information would help candidates decide whether or not to withdraw,
and would help voters decide whether to encourage their favorite
candidates to withdraw.
We've seen many examples posted here showing how, given plain Instant
Runoff, sincere votes such as ABC can backfire and elect C. (C could
have been defeated if those voters had instead ranked B first.)
JITW//IRV would allow candidate A to respect the ABC voters' intense
preference for B over C, whenever they are intense enough, by
withdrawing from contention, without forcing those voters to
insincerely rank B first.
France already uses a related system. They use a runoff system in
which any candidate with at least 12.5% of the vote in the primary
qualifies for a runoff. They permit candidates to voluntarily
withdraw before the runoff, and that is exactly what most candidates
do when they predict they'd otherwise be spoilers.
Some people may argue that JITW// would create the possibility of
backroom deals among the candidates which would defeat the will of
the voters. It should be pointed out that most candidates would be
forcibly eliminated by the //IRV (or //Condorcet) anyway; only
"dominant" candidates would be able to improve the outcome by
withdrawing.
Also, the proportional representation systems (and non-proportional
multiparty systems) which many people advocate have an even worse
backroom deal problem, after elections when a majority coalition is
being cobbled together to run the legislature and (maybe) select the
prime minister: In that situation each legislator has a full vote to
sell as s/he pleases, whereas in JITW// systems a withdrawing
candidate is merely stepping out of the way of voters' preferences.
JITW guarantees that no candidate can be made into a spoiler against
his/her will. (If I correctly understand the Gibbard-Satterthwaite
"manipulability" theorem, only methods which permit just-in-time
withdrawal rigorously satisfy this "no spoiling" criterion. One
might go further and say that JITW moots the theorem, since the order-
reversal tactic backfires by giving some power to one's "greater
evil": the power to undo the effect of the reversal.) So given JITW
there is no deterrent against competing and no need for a party to
nominate only one candidate. (Hence partisan primaries would be of
little importance. They'd still be of utmost importance given plain
IRV.)
JITW also allows any voter to vote sincerely, with no strategic
dilemma, whenever she trusts her more preferred candidate(s) to
withdraw when necessary to defeat her least preferred candidate(s).
(Given JITW//IRV or JITW//Condorcet, she can also safely rank her
more preferred candidates ahead of the others whenever she believes
they would surely lose anyway given IRV or Condorcet.) Presumably,
questions about the circumstances in which candidates would withdraw
would be asked during the pre-election campaigns, and voters would
tend to downrank candidates whose answers are troubling.
JITW//Plurality, clearly the simplest of the plausible methods, would
also work well whenever supporters can trust their more-preferred
candidates to withdraw when needed to defeat their less-preferred
candidates.
* *
As mentioned above, another solution to Donald's problem is plain
Condorcet, since its definition doesn't include any language about
circularity. It could on occasion elect a candidate which is not in
the top cycle, in fact, due to that omission from its definition, but
since it would create competition to be in the center we can expect
that even in that case the winner would be reasonably close to the
top cycle. (That's no worse than the "reasonably close" argument
which is used by some conservative political scientists to justify
keeping the two-party system.) JITW//Condorcet would solve that
minor problem, since one or more members of the top cycle would have
the incentive to withdraw in order to defeat that slightly worse
candidate and elect another member of the top cycle. I believe that
JITW//Condorcet would in practice perform as well as Smith//Condorcet
(which led the 1996 EM poll, just ahead of plain Condorcet). Perhaps
even better, because candidates would need to avoid slinging mud at
others whom they may later need to coax to withdraw.
Yet another solution to Donald's problem is the method advocated by
Bruce Anderson, which Bruce calls "Regular-Champion" (RC). It's also
known as Copeland//Plurality. RC calculates each candidate's "won-
loss" record: a pair-defeat is a loss and a pair-win is a win. The
candidate with the best won-loss record is elected (Copeland). If
there's a tie for best won-loss record (which may or may not be due
to circularity; the definition doesn't need to mention circularity)
then the tie is broken by looking only at each voter's first choice
(the //Plurality tie-breaking component of RC).
Since Donald's problem is really about how to explain methods, not
with the technical merits of methods, RC probably has an advantage
there over methods which explicitly refer to the top cycle. It
doesn't need to use language which explains circularity, since the
candidate(s) with the best won-loss record must be in the top cycle
anyway. (That's easy to prove.) RC seems less meritorious than some
other better pairwise methods, though... recall our discussions about
its "rich party problem" and about its greater susceptibility to
order-reversal and truncation. Also Copeland is highly prone to "win-
loss" ties, even when voters don't strategize, so the //Plurality tie-
breaker procedure would often be invoked.
JITW//RC is probably an excellent method, and I hope Bruce Anderson
will examine it. It might be easier to explain than JITW//IRV or
JITW//Condorcet, but this is difficult to predict.
I haven't yet read Blake's description of his "Path Voting" method,
so I don't know whether it needs to include the language of
circularity. If it gives each candidate a score and elects the one
with the best score, as do plain Condorcet and RC, then it probably
doesn't refer to the top cycle.
> As more and more voters decide to only make one choice the
> Condorcet method will be forced to function using lower and lower scales.
-snip-
This assertion that voters would "learn" to make only one choice
(radical truncation) is one which Donald has been repeating for a
long time, but to my knowledge he has never provided a convincing
reason. As far as I know, he has never posted even one example which
would illustrate why, given the best pairwise methods, voters would
have an incentive to truncate.
Why is it more likely voters would foolishly "learn" to truncate
given the best pairwise methods than that voters would learn, given
plain Instant Runoff, to rank the compromise ahead of a more
preferred candidate? Many examples have been posted showing how
failing to rank the compromise ahead of one's favorite can result in
the election of one's "greater evil", and we know empirically that
voters are willing to compromise when necessary. Those examples
indicate a clear incentive in Instant Runoff for voters to order-
reverse, abandoning their desire to express their preference for
their more preferred choices.
Perhaps Donald didn't understand the "truncation resistance" property
of the Condorcet and Smith//Condorcet methods which led the 1996 poll
in the EM maillist. Some other variations, such as measuring the
size of a candidate's pairloss by taking the margin of difference in
that pairing (instead of by counting the voters who ranked the
pairwinner ahead of the pairloser), would be more susceptible to
truncation. Truncation might be done strategically given methods
which aren't truncation-resistant, or innocently because a voter
wanted to finish voting early. Truncation resistance means that the
voter does not have a strategic incentive to rank only one, since
that strategy won't help the voter. And it means that innocent
truncation won't affect outcomes either (unless a lot of voters
foolishly truncate the compromise candidate who needed their votes).
Pairwise methods treat the ranking of only one candidate as if the
voter had ranked all other candidates equally last. It's tallied as
indifference in the pairings between those other candidates. A voter
whose sincere preference order is "ABC", if he voted just "A", would
have the direct effect of making his "greater evil" C less beaten in
the "B vs. C" pairing, and maybe change that pairing from "B beat C"
to "C beat B". Why does Donald think voters would learn to do that,
when it so clearly and perversely helps their greater evil? That
dubious strategy would have no effect on the "A vs. B" pairing, since
by voting "ABC" the voter is counted just as fully for A in the "A
vs. B" and the "A vs. C" pairings as if he'd voted just "A".
The closest I can come to showing how voter behavior related to
what's asserted by Donald might sometimes occur is this: It is
possible to show how supporters of a candidate whom they expect would
beat all others pairwise, if all voters voted sincerely, would have
an incentive to downrank the candidate of a faction they feared might
successfully attempt massive order-reversal. If the example includes
only three candidates, then that downranking could take the form of
truncation: B>A>C becomes B>A=C which can be expediently voted as
"B" (since unranked candidates are treated as if they'd been ranked
equally last). (In important elections we can expect more than three
candidates so the downranking would not be the same as ranking only
one; it would be changing A>B>C>D>E to A>B=C>D>E.)
By pre-announcing that defensive downranking strategy and
demonstrating their will to execute it when voting, the supporters of
the compromise candidate would deter order-reversal.
That strategy would not be useful to most voters. It would only be
useful to the supporters of the (centrist compromise) candidate who
would be elected anyway if all voters voted sincerely. There's no
reason to believe that other voters would behave that way, especially
since if they did they'd eliminate the only reason (i.e., the threat
of offensive order-reversal by a minority wing) for anyone to ever do
it.
Offensive truncation is a useless strategy in methods which are
truncation-resistant. Order-reversal could be effective. Defensive
downranking could only be useful for certain voters, the supporters
of the compromise. If truncation (instead of reversal) were
routinely used by other voters, as Donald claims it would, then there
wouldn't be a reason for any voter to defensively downrank!
Example 1: Resistance to truncation
46: A <-- These truncated their ABC preference. (But why?)
10: BAC <-- sincere, no incentive to truncate or reverse
10: BCA <-- sincere, no incentive to truncate or reverse
34: CBA <-- sincere, no incentive to truncate or reverse
Pairing x>A x>B x>C
-------- ---- ---- ----
A vs. B? 54L 46
A vs. C? 44 56L
B vs. C? 34L 20
---- ---- ----
Largest loss: 54 34 56
B (34) is still elected, so there's no incentive to truncate.
Example 2: Defensive downranking by a few deters massive reversal.
23: ABC <-- sincere
23: ACB <-- Most of these offensively reversed their ABC.
10: B <-- These defensively downranked A from B>A>C to B>A=C.
10: BCA <-- sincere, no incentive to misrepresent
34: CBA <-- sincere, no incentive to misrepresent
Pairing x>A x>B x>C
-------- ---- ---- ----
A vs. B? 54L 46
A vs. C? 44 46L
B vs. C? 80L 20
---- ---- ----
Largest loss: 54 80 46
C (46) is elected, deterring reversal by making it backfire.
The 10 BAC voters easily win this game of "chicken" played
with the devious ABC voters who threaten reversal.
Note how, in both examples, the CBA voters have a very strong
disincentive against truncating. If any of them truncate, that would
reduce the size of A's loss in the "A vs. B" pairing from 54 to
something smaller, which doesn't help C and could easily help elect A
(their "greater evil"). If they did what Donald claims they would,
they'd have to be pretty silly.
---Steve (Steve Eppley seppley at alumni.caltech.edu)
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list