FPTP family theory, REDLOG shadowing
Markus Schulze
schulze at sol.physik.tu-berlin.de
Mon Dec 13 04:14:35 PST 1999
Dear Craig,
you wrote (13 Dec 1999):
> I'll simplify that "multiwinner participation axiom" definition I put
> in a previous message.
>
> I had written this:
> -------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Definition: (Q2), "multiwinner participation (axiom)" rule. (11-Dec-99):
>
> (For All V)(For All p)(For All Q)[
> [(For All q)[(q in Q) => (p = trunc(q,length(p)))]] =>
> (For All t) [(0<=t)(#t=#Q)(#(p.W(V))=#(p.W(V+t*Q))) .=>
> (Satisf(W(V),p) <= Satisf(W(V+t*Q),p))]]
> -------------------------------------------------------------------------
>
> If 'SPC' holds then Q can be removed.
> SPC says that a candidate's win-lose state is unaffected by subsequent
> preferences.
> For example, p=(ABC), Q=((ABCD),(ABCE)), t=(2,5)
> V+t*Q= V+(1*t)p=
> 2 ABCD 7 ABC
> 5 ABCE S
> S
> In these 2 examples, if A (or B, or C) wins one then it wins the other.
> Similarly for B and C but not D
> and E.
> Hence p.W(V+t*Q) = p.W(V+(1*t)p), in this case:
> {A,B,C}.W(V+t*Q) = {A,B,C}.W(V+7p)
>
> Quite probably those persons that would want to impose a participation
> axiom would also impose SPC too. If SPC is not imposed then the rule
> has been made weaker.
>
> Also the rule can be altered and made more restrictive, by altering
> #(p.W(V))=#(p.W(V+tp)) into #(p.W(V))<=#(p.W(V+tp)). That would
> would require that the satisfaction value increases when the number
> of winners increases.
>
> -------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Definition: (Q2), "multiwinner participation axiom" rule. (13-Dec-99):
>
> (For All V)(For All p)(For All t) [
> (0<=t)(#(p.W(V))<=#(p.W(V+tp))) .=>
> (Satisf(W(V),p) <= Satisf(W(V+tp),p))]]
> -------------------------------------------------------------------------
>
> The Satisf function can be removed.
>
> (Satisf(W,p) <= Satisf(X,p)) = (For All j=1..length(p)).[ G(W,X,p,j) ]
>
> G(W,X,p,j) = ((W.trunc(p,j-1) = X.trunc(p,j-1)) => (W.{p[j]} <= X.{p[j])})
>
> ("<=" is subset, so: (W.{x} <= X.{x}) = ((x in W) => (x in X))
>
> The rule as defined may not be beyond being improved.
>
> Here are some example alterations. (Papers are not remarked.)
>
> Write a n:A+B+CDEF to mean that the paper (ABCDEF) has weight n and that
> {A,B} = ({A,B,C,D,E,F}.Winners).
>
> Let Z(p) = [#(p.W(V)), #(p.W(V+tp)); Satisf(W(V),p), Satisf(W(V+tp),p)]
> The rule fails the particular alteration if this is false:
> (z1<=z2)=>(z3<=z4).
>
> (0:AB)--(9:AB+): Z(AB)=(0,1; 0,1/4), Allowed
> (0:AB+)--(9:AB): Z(AB)=(1,0; _,_), Allowed
> Allow the adding of AB to causes B to start losing
>
> (0:ABC+DE+FG)--(9:ABC+DE+FG+): Z(ABCDEFG)=(2,3;5/32,5/32+1/128), Allowed
> (0:ABC+DE+FG+)--(9:ABC+DE+FG): Z(ABCDEFG)=(3,2; _, _), Allowed
> (0:A+BCD)--(9:AB+C+D+):
> Z(AB) =(1,1; 1/2, 1/4), Not allowed
> Z(ABCD)=(1,3; 1/2, 1/4+1/8+1/16), Not allowed
>
> I do consider this rule to be worth imposing.
Example (1 seat; 21 voters; Alternative Voting):
7 voters vote A > B > C > D.
6 voters vote B > A > C > D.
5 voters vote C > B > A > D.
3 voters vote D > C > B > A.
Candidate A is elected. But if the three DCBA voters had
truncated their votes and had voted only for candidate D,
then candidate B would have been elected.
Could you -please- explain why Alternative Voting meets your
multiwinner participation axiom so that Alternative Voting is
not "too defective to be used in practice" (20 Oct 1999)?
Markus Schulze
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list