[EM] Re: majority rule, mutinous pirates, and voter strategy
Juho Laatu
juho4880 at yahoo.co.uk
Wed Mar 16 06:58:10 PST 2005
Hello James,
I wrote a long mail. Sorry about that. No need to reply on everything
word in it. I however felt that it is worth writing all the text, just
in case it would trigger some useful thoughts. Simple answer "thanks
but I'm not convinced of the merits of non-Smith-set candidates yet" is
also enough :-).
Best Regards,
Juho
> About your "least additional votes" method: Correct me if I'm wrong,
> but
> I think that your method is equivalent to minimax (margins).
Correct. Didn't want to reveal that right away. Fresh thinking
requested. :-)
If the maximum defeat margin of some candidate is n, she needs exactly
n+1 additional votes to become a Condorcet winner.
> Just clarifying... When you say a larger majority, you seem to mean a
> majority with a wider margin.
Yes, sorry about not being more exact. All my terms in the mail (e.g.
"large majority") referred to margins. (And yes, term "narrowest
majority" is more appropriate than "smallest majority".)
I tend to see margins as "natural" and winning votes as something that
deviates from the more natural margins but that might be used somewhere
to eliminate strategic voting. (not a very scientific description but I
don't have any better short explanation available :-) )
> A large majority who is unhappy with the change? I would say that
> there
> is a large *minority* (201 voters) that is unhappy with the change.
I meant that when X was the captain people wanted to change him to A, B
or C with a small margin of votes. But later when e.g. C became the
captain people wanted to change him to B with a large margin. Only a
minority wanted to change C to X. But the point is that people
(majority of them) are now "less happy" or "more mutinous" because of
the problematic B>C relationship. I'm thus just measuring general
happiness and risk of mutiny without paying attention to whom people
would elect as captain in the current situation. The election method
could be so clever that it would elect X (the candidate with least risk
of mutiny) even if the people would not make the switch themselves in a
mutiny. (Are election methods allowed to be more clever than the voters
when picking up the winner?)
> it's hard to say,
> because we only have ordinal information here, nothing about utility,
> strength of preference, 'approval', etc.
I think it is the nature of (basic) Condorcet methods not to take into
account how strong the preferences are. Taking also strengths into
account would be wonderful but I guess it is the problems with
strategical voting that have kept us away from this ideal target. When
talking about Condorcet based methods I tend to limit myself to this
"order only" mode.
(I however think that your cardinal pairwise method adds something to
this plain Condorcet tradition without taking all the rating related
problems in => worth another discussion.)
> Violating an unambiguous majority preference (e.g. A>X) is a *larger*
> problem than violating a majority preference that is contradicted by
> another majority preference (e.g. A>C), because the former is always
> avoidable, and the latter is unavoidable in the case of a majority rule
> cycle.
I think all the majorities are unambiguous (because that is what the
voters told us). A>X could be called "loopless", if we want to describe
how it is different from the others. Both electing X and electing A
violate a majority opinion. One can avoid violating A>X by not electing
X (= select one of the Smith candidates). But one can also avoid
violating e.g. A>B by not electing B. All of the individual preferences
are thus avoidable. And all the Smith loop violations can be avoided by
electing X. I guess the key target of my pirate example is to
demonstrate that in some (rare) situations violating A>X could be a
smaller crime than violating one of the Smith loop preferences. (And my
thinking is not based that much on paths but on utility of each captain
candidate separately.)
> In your pirate example, there are no compromise
> candidates; the pirate electorate is very badly polarized.
I agree. The basic setting is four parties of about equal size. I think
this situation is quite normal. What is exceptional is the strength of
the loop. My understanding however is that strong loops may occur also
in real life - considerably stronger than ones between three parties of
equal size as a result of some random votes. Also sincere, not only as
a result of a voting strategy.
> But what if multiple dissatisfied groups arose at once?
> Then the X supporters would be in desperate trouble (as would
> supporters
> of any other candidate in a similar situation).
Yes. I think now we come to the question if "mutiny" is the "only
correct" real life criterion or if there are also others. I claim that
"mutiny" is one well defined criterion that is useful is some
situations and directly points out the correct voting method (MinMax
with margins).
Mutiny of everyone against one is one candidate for another real life
criterion. I think mutiny to replace one with one is however the most
useful and typical case (both in the ship and in politics). This
"mutiny for anyone else" would also give support to sticking to the
Smith set when electing the winner. I'm however afraid that these
majorities can not be summed up (=> not a strong case to support
sticking to the Smith set). (Note also that a Condorcet winner that has
not been the #1 favourite of any of the voters has a risk of yet
another type of mutiny ("everyone thinks he is not the best").)
There may be also other real life criteria that could be used to
characterise (or define) different alternative single winner election
types / needs. I think the current paradigm is that there are only one
type of single winner elections (i.e. rules are the same irrespective
of what the context is (e.g. captain, president, holiday resort or
favourite fruit election); one method serves all single winner needs).
I tried to prove that eliminating risk of mutiny is one such need, but
I don't have any evidence that it is the only one that is needed.
> I began to feel that there was
> something logically inconsistent about insisting on the Condorcet
> winner,
> but abandoning all strict majority rule requirements when no Condorcet
> winner exists.
In my mind one important borderline is cycles. Newtonian physics
(=linear ordering) applies as long as there are no loops. Condorcet
winner is a very natural concept in this world. But when loops emerge
the ideal linear ordering is broken. To me the linear order of Smith
sets (the top cycle + bigger ones) (or "loop groupings") is not the
most tempting way forward since it seems to hide possibly bigger group
preferences inside the "loop groupings" than what the strength of
preferences between the groupings are. As I mentioned earlier, there is
a risk of trying to make the group opinions look like linear (personal)
preferences. I think the drawing (and imagining) techniques may lead us
to false conclusions. As a result I have been interested also in
criteria that simply evaluate candidates one by one.
> I would say none of the above candidates are a sufficient compromise
> candidate. I would suggest that the pirates try a bit harder to find a
> compromise captain (perhaps someone who has spent several years in each
> country). Failing that, I would suggest that the four factions should
> go
> their separate ways, finding boats that are manned by more like-minded
> seafarers.
That is not allowed :-). We had an election with four candidates. And
elections are not supposed to cause countries to break into separate
smaller countries. The best single winner election method must be
capable of electing one (the best) of these candidates. Since you say
that you want to stick to the Smith set, I guess your answer must be A,
B or C. That would violate the "least risk of mutiny" criterion. Does
this mean that there is no need for election methods that try find the
optimal candidate by minimizing the risk of mutiny.
More information about the Election-Methods
mailing list